Strong induction and vacuous truth












1












$begingroup$


I was pondering a bit more about this question regarding being able to "omit" the base case in a proof by strong induction due to vacuous truth. The post states:




Strong induction proves a sequence of statements $P(0), P(1), …$ by
proving the implication



"If $P(m)$ is true for all nonnegative integers $m$ less than $n$,
then $P(n)$ is true."



for every nonnegative integer $n$. There is no need for a separate
base case, because the $n=0$ instance of the implication is the base
case, vacuously.




However, if we consider $n=0$, we would have that the statement is vacuously true, which I would take to mean that the implication is true regardless of the validity of $P(0)$. However, clearly it's necessary for $P(0)$ to hold for an induction proof to be valid. So I'm confused on how, by omitting the base case, $n=0$ isn't just a tautology, making the implication true regardless of whether $P(0)$ actually holds.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    For $n=0$, the premise ''If P(m) is true for all nonneg. integers m less than 0'' is vacuously true. But its an implication and so you need to prove that P(0) is true.
    $endgroup$
    – Wuestenfux
    Jan 2 at 9:29










  • $begingroup$
    @Wuestenfux Ah, so it isn't the implication that's vacuously true, it's the premise is vacuously true, so since $T Rightarrow P(0) Leftrightarrow P(0)$, it precisely boils down to proving $P(0)$?
    $endgroup$
    – rb612
    Jan 2 at 9:32
















1












$begingroup$


I was pondering a bit more about this question regarding being able to "omit" the base case in a proof by strong induction due to vacuous truth. The post states:




Strong induction proves a sequence of statements $P(0), P(1), …$ by
proving the implication



"If $P(m)$ is true for all nonnegative integers $m$ less than $n$,
then $P(n)$ is true."



for every nonnegative integer $n$. There is no need for a separate
base case, because the $n=0$ instance of the implication is the base
case, vacuously.




However, if we consider $n=0$, we would have that the statement is vacuously true, which I would take to mean that the implication is true regardless of the validity of $P(0)$. However, clearly it's necessary for $P(0)$ to hold for an induction proof to be valid. So I'm confused on how, by omitting the base case, $n=0$ isn't just a tautology, making the implication true regardless of whether $P(0)$ actually holds.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    For $n=0$, the premise ''If P(m) is true for all nonneg. integers m less than 0'' is vacuously true. But its an implication and so you need to prove that P(0) is true.
    $endgroup$
    – Wuestenfux
    Jan 2 at 9:29










  • $begingroup$
    @Wuestenfux Ah, so it isn't the implication that's vacuously true, it's the premise is vacuously true, so since $T Rightarrow P(0) Leftrightarrow P(0)$, it precisely boils down to proving $P(0)$?
    $endgroup$
    – rb612
    Jan 2 at 9:32














1












1








1





$begingroup$


I was pondering a bit more about this question regarding being able to "omit" the base case in a proof by strong induction due to vacuous truth. The post states:




Strong induction proves a sequence of statements $P(0), P(1), …$ by
proving the implication



"If $P(m)$ is true for all nonnegative integers $m$ less than $n$,
then $P(n)$ is true."



for every nonnegative integer $n$. There is no need for a separate
base case, because the $n=0$ instance of the implication is the base
case, vacuously.




However, if we consider $n=0$, we would have that the statement is vacuously true, which I would take to mean that the implication is true regardless of the validity of $P(0)$. However, clearly it's necessary for $P(0)$ to hold for an induction proof to be valid. So I'm confused on how, by omitting the base case, $n=0$ isn't just a tautology, making the implication true regardless of whether $P(0)$ actually holds.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




I was pondering a bit more about this question regarding being able to "omit" the base case in a proof by strong induction due to vacuous truth. The post states:




Strong induction proves a sequence of statements $P(0), P(1), …$ by
proving the implication



"If $P(m)$ is true for all nonnegative integers $m$ less than $n$,
then $P(n)$ is true."



for every nonnegative integer $n$. There is no need for a separate
base case, because the $n=0$ instance of the implication is the base
case, vacuously.




However, if we consider $n=0$, we would have that the statement is vacuously true, which I would take to mean that the implication is true regardless of the validity of $P(0)$. However, clearly it's necessary for $P(0)$ to hold for an induction proof to be valid. So I'm confused on how, by omitting the base case, $n=0$ isn't just a tautology, making the implication true regardless of whether $P(0)$ actually holds.







proof-writing induction first-order-logic






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Jan 2 at 9:23









rb612rb612

1,9281924




1,9281924








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    For $n=0$, the premise ''If P(m) is true for all nonneg. integers m less than 0'' is vacuously true. But its an implication and so you need to prove that P(0) is true.
    $endgroup$
    – Wuestenfux
    Jan 2 at 9:29










  • $begingroup$
    @Wuestenfux Ah, so it isn't the implication that's vacuously true, it's the premise is vacuously true, so since $T Rightarrow P(0) Leftrightarrow P(0)$, it precisely boils down to proving $P(0)$?
    $endgroup$
    – rb612
    Jan 2 at 9:32














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    For $n=0$, the premise ''If P(m) is true for all nonneg. integers m less than 0'' is vacuously true. But its an implication and so you need to prove that P(0) is true.
    $endgroup$
    – Wuestenfux
    Jan 2 at 9:29










  • $begingroup$
    @Wuestenfux Ah, so it isn't the implication that's vacuously true, it's the premise is vacuously true, so since $T Rightarrow P(0) Leftrightarrow P(0)$, it precisely boils down to proving $P(0)$?
    $endgroup$
    – rb612
    Jan 2 at 9:32








2




2




$begingroup$
For $n=0$, the premise ''If P(m) is true for all nonneg. integers m less than 0'' is vacuously true. But its an implication and so you need to prove that P(0) is true.
$endgroup$
– Wuestenfux
Jan 2 at 9:29




$begingroup$
For $n=0$, the premise ''If P(m) is true for all nonneg. integers m less than 0'' is vacuously true. But its an implication and so you need to prove that P(0) is true.
$endgroup$
– Wuestenfux
Jan 2 at 9:29












$begingroup$
@Wuestenfux Ah, so it isn't the implication that's vacuously true, it's the premise is vacuously true, so since $T Rightarrow P(0) Leftrightarrow P(0)$, it precisely boils down to proving $P(0)$?
$endgroup$
– rb612
Jan 2 at 9:32




$begingroup$
@Wuestenfux Ah, so it isn't the implication that's vacuously true, it's the premise is vacuously true, so since $T Rightarrow P(0) Leftrightarrow P(0)$, it precisely boils down to proving $P(0)$?
$endgroup$
– rb612
Jan 2 at 9:32










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















3












$begingroup$

Strong (or : complete) induction is :




$(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)] to (∀n) P(n)$.




So, in order to conclude with $(∀n) P(n)$ we have to show that : $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)]$ holds.



If I understand well, your concern is with $n=0$.



In that case, we have :




$(∀m)(m < 0 to P(m)) to P(0)$.




But $(m < 0 to P(m))$ is vacuously true (there are no $m < 0$). Thus, the conditional amounts to : $text T to P(0)$ and there is only one possibility to satisfies it : when $P(0)$ is true.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    To the proposer: So the assertion that $[forall mge 0;(m<nto P(m))]to P(n)$ holds for all $nge 0,$ does imply that the "base-case" $P(0)$ is true.
    $endgroup$
    – DanielWainfleet
    Jan 2 at 11:36



















1












$begingroup$

In strong induction, you show that each instance of $P(n)$ can be reduced to one or more cases $P(m)$ with $m<n$, so if all smaller cases are known to be true then case $n$ follows. The distinction from normal induction is that you don't necessarily know what values of $m$ $P(n)$ will reduce to, in particular it is not necessarily $m=n-1$, so you need to know all previous cases. A simple example is to prove that every integer at least $2$ is a product of primes: for a given integer $ngeq 2$, either $n$ is prime (so trivially true) or $n$ is a product of two integers $a,bgeq 2$. Now $a,b<n$, so both are products of primes, and we're done.



In this case there is no need for a separate base case. If $n=2$, what happens is that there are no integers $a,b$ with $2leq a,b<n$, so the second case above can't happen and $n$ must be prime. Here your reduction to smaller $m$ happens to include a proof of the base case.



However, normally what happens is that the reduction to smaller case(s) doesn't work for the smallest value of $n$, and you do need a separate base case. For example, you might be trying to prove the same statement for $ngeq 1$, and then you need to deal with $n=1$ (the empty product) separately, since the statement that $n$ is prime or can be written as the product of two smaller positive integers doesn't hold for $n=1$.



For any strong induction one of these two things happens. If the proof of the reduction breaks down for $n=0$ (or whatever the minimum $n$ is), you have to do the base case separately; if it doesn't, this gives a reason why $P(0)$ is vacuously true.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$














    Your Answer








    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3059273%2fstrong-induction-and-vacuous-truth%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    3












    $begingroup$

    Strong (or : complete) induction is :




    $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)] to (∀n) P(n)$.




    So, in order to conclude with $(∀n) P(n)$ we have to show that : $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)]$ holds.



    If I understand well, your concern is with $n=0$.



    In that case, we have :




    $(∀m)(m < 0 to P(m)) to P(0)$.




    But $(m < 0 to P(m))$ is vacuously true (there are no $m < 0$). Thus, the conditional amounts to : $text T to P(0)$ and there is only one possibility to satisfies it : when $P(0)$ is true.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      To the proposer: So the assertion that $[forall mge 0;(m<nto P(m))]to P(n)$ holds for all $nge 0,$ does imply that the "base-case" $P(0)$ is true.
      $endgroup$
      – DanielWainfleet
      Jan 2 at 11:36
















    3












    $begingroup$

    Strong (or : complete) induction is :




    $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)] to (∀n) P(n)$.




    So, in order to conclude with $(∀n) P(n)$ we have to show that : $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)]$ holds.



    If I understand well, your concern is with $n=0$.



    In that case, we have :




    $(∀m)(m < 0 to P(m)) to P(0)$.




    But $(m < 0 to P(m))$ is vacuously true (there are no $m < 0$). Thus, the conditional amounts to : $text T to P(0)$ and there is only one possibility to satisfies it : when $P(0)$ is true.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      To the proposer: So the assertion that $[forall mge 0;(m<nto P(m))]to P(n)$ holds for all $nge 0,$ does imply that the "base-case" $P(0)$ is true.
      $endgroup$
      – DanielWainfleet
      Jan 2 at 11:36














    3












    3








    3





    $begingroup$

    Strong (or : complete) induction is :




    $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)] to (∀n) P(n)$.




    So, in order to conclude with $(∀n) P(n)$ we have to show that : $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)]$ holds.



    If I understand well, your concern is with $n=0$.



    In that case, we have :




    $(∀m)(m < 0 to P(m)) to P(0)$.




    But $(m < 0 to P(m))$ is vacuously true (there are no $m < 0$). Thus, the conditional amounts to : $text T to P(0)$ and there is only one possibility to satisfies it : when $P(0)$ is true.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    Strong (or : complete) induction is :




    $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)] to (∀n) P(n)$.




    So, in order to conclude with $(∀n) P(n)$ we have to show that : $(∀n)[(∀m)(m < n to P(m)) to P(n)]$ holds.



    If I understand well, your concern is with $n=0$.



    In that case, we have :




    $(∀m)(m < 0 to P(m)) to P(0)$.




    But $(m < 0 to P(m))$ is vacuously true (there are no $m < 0$). Thus, the conditional amounts to : $text T to P(0)$ and there is only one possibility to satisfies it : when $P(0)$ is true.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Jan 2 at 9:38









    Mauro ALLEGRANZAMauro ALLEGRANZA

    68.3k449117




    68.3k449117












    • $begingroup$
      To the proposer: So the assertion that $[forall mge 0;(m<nto P(m))]to P(n)$ holds for all $nge 0,$ does imply that the "base-case" $P(0)$ is true.
      $endgroup$
      – DanielWainfleet
      Jan 2 at 11:36


















    • $begingroup$
      To the proposer: So the assertion that $[forall mge 0;(m<nto P(m))]to P(n)$ holds for all $nge 0,$ does imply that the "base-case" $P(0)$ is true.
      $endgroup$
      – DanielWainfleet
      Jan 2 at 11:36
















    $begingroup$
    To the proposer: So the assertion that $[forall mge 0;(m<nto P(m))]to P(n)$ holds for all $nge 0,$ does imply that the "base-case" $P(0)$ is true.
    $endgroup$
    – DanielWainfleet
    Jan 2 at 11:36




    $begingroup$
    To the proposer: So the assertion that $[forall mge 0;(m<nto P(m))]to P(n)$ holds for all $nge 0,$ does imply that the "base-case" $P(0)$ is true.
    $endgroup$
    – DanielWainfleet
    Jan 2 at 11:36











    1












    $begingroup$

    In strong induction, you show that each instance of $P(n)$ can be reduced to one or more cases $P(m)$ with $m<n$, so if all smaller cases are known to be true then case $n$ follows. The distinction from normal induction is that you don't necessarily know what values of $m$ $P(n)$ will reduce to, in particular it is not necessarily $m=n-1$, so you need to know all previous cases. A simple example is to prove that every integer at least $2$ is a product of primes: for a given integer $ngeq 2$, either $n$ is prime (so trivially true) or $n$ is a product of two integers $a,bgeq 2$. Now $a,b<n$, so both are products of primes, and we're done.



    In this case there is no need for a separate base case. If $n=2$, what happens is that there are no integers $a,b$ with $2leq a,b<n$, so the second case above can't happen and $n$ must be prime. Here your reduction to smaller $m$ happens to include a proof of the base case.



    However, normally what happens is that the reduction to smaller case(s) doesn't work for the smallest value of $n$, and you do need a separate base case. For example, you might be trying to prove the same statement for $ngeq 1$, and then you need to deal with $n=1$ (the empty product) separately, since the statement that $n$ is prime or can be written as the product of two smaller positive integers doesn't hold for $n=1$.



    For any strong induction one of these two things happens. If the proof of the reduction breaks down for $n=0$ (or whatever the minimum $n$ is), you have to do the base case separately; if it doesn't, this gives a reason why $P(0)$ is vacuously true.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      1












      $begingroup$

      In strong induction, you show that each instance of $P(n)$ can be reduced to one or more cases $P(m)$ with $m<n$, so if all smaller cases are known to be true then case $n$ follows. The distinction from normal induction is that you don't necessarily know what values of $m$ $P(n)$ will reduce to, in particular it is not necessarily $m=n-1$, so you need to know all previous cases. A simple example is to prove that every integer at least $2$ is a product of primes: for a given integer $ngeq 2$, either $n$ is prime (so trivially true) or $n$ is a product of two integers $a,bgeq 2$. Now $a,b<n$, so both are products of primes, and we're done.



      In this case there is no need for a separate base case. If $n=2$, what happens is that there are no integers $a,b$ with $2leq a,b<n$, so the second case above can't happen and $n$ must be prime. Here your reduction to smaller $m$ happens to include a proof of the base case.



      However, normally what happens is that the reduction to smaller case(s) doesn't work for the smallest value of $n$, and you do need a separate base case. For example, you might be trying to prove the same statement for $ngeq 1$, and then you need to deal with $n=1$ (the empty product) separately, since the statement that $n$ is prime or can be written as the product of two smaller positive integers doesn't hold for $n=1$.



      For any strong induction one of these two things happens. If the proof of the reduction breaks down for $n=0$ (or whatever the minimum $n$ is), you have to do the base case separately; if it doesn't, this gives a reason why $P(0)$ is vacuously true.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        1












        1








        1





        $begingroup$

        In strong induction, you show that each instance of $P(n)$ can be reduced to one or more cases $P(m)$ with $m<n$, so if all smaller cases are known to be true then case $n$ follows. The distinction from normal induction is that you don't necessarily know what values of $m$ $P(n)$ will reduce to, in particular it is not necessarily $m=n-1$, so you need to know all previous cases. A simple example is to prove that every integer at least $2$ is a product of primes: for a given integer $ngeq 2$, either $n$ is prime (so trivially true) or $n$ is a product of two integers $a,bgeq 2$. Now $a,b<n$, so both are products of primes, and we're done.



        In this case there is no need for a separate base case. If $n=2$, what happens is that there are no integers $a,b$ with $2leq a,b<n$, so the second case above can't happen and $n$ must be prime. Here your reduction to smaller $m$ happens to include a proof of the base case.



        However, normally what happens is that the reduction to smaller case(s) doesn't work for the smallest value of $n$, and you do need a separate base case. For example, you might be trying to prove the same statement for $ngeq 1$, and then you need to deal with $n=1$ (the empty product) separately, since the statement that $n$ is prime or can be written as the product of two smaller positive integers doesn't hold for $n=1$.



        For any strong induction one of these two things happens. If the proof of the reduction breaks down for $n=0$ (or whatever the minimum $n$ is), you have to do the base case separately; if it doesn't, this gives a reason why $P(0)$ is vacuously true.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        In strong induction, you show that each instance of $P(n)$ can be reduced to one or more cases $P(m)$ with $m<n$, so if all smaller cases are known to be true then case $n$ follows. The distinction from normal induction is that you don't necessarily know what values of $m$ $P(n)$ will reduce to, in particular it is not necessarily $m=n-1$, so you need to know all previous cases. A simple example is to prove that every integer at least $2$ is a product of primes: for a given integer $ngeq 2$, either $n$ is prime (so trivially true) or $n$ is a product of two integers $a,bgeq 2$. Now $a,b<n$, so both are products of primes, and we're done.



        In this case there is no need for a separate base case. If $n=2$, what happens is that there are no integers $a,b$ with $2leq a,b<n$, so the second case above can't happen and $n$ must be prime. Here your reduction to smaller $m$ happens to include a proof of the base case.



        However, normally what happens is that the reduction to smaller case(s) doesn't work for the smallest value of $n$, and you do need a separate base case. For example, you might be trying to prove the same statement for $ngeq 1$, and then you need to deal with $n=1$ (the empty product) separately, since the statement that $n$ is prime or can be written as the product of two smaller positive integers doesn't hold for $n=1$.



        For any strong induction one of these two things happens. If the proof of the reduction breaks down for $n=0$ (or whatever the minimum $n$ is), you have to do the base case separately; if it doesn't, this gives a reason why $P(0)$ is vacuously true.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Jan 2 at 9:37









        Especially LimeEspecially Lime

        22.9k23059




        22.9k23059






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3059273%2fstrong-induction-and-vacuous-truth%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            How to change which sound is reproduced for terminal bell?

            Can I use Tabulator js library in my java Spring + Thymeleaf project?

            Title Spacing in Bjornstrup Chapter, Removing Chapter Number From Contents