Is there a partial recursive function mapping $e$ to the least element of $W_e$?












1












$begingroup$


Is there a partial recursive function $f$ that maps $e$ to the least element of $W_e$ if $W_eneq varnothing$?



Can we apply the $mu$-operator (minimization) to a partially decidable predicate to get a partial recursive function (as in defining $f(x)=mu z(zin W_e)$ if $W_eneqvarnothing$ and undefined otherwise, since $zin W_e$ is partially decidable)?



My guess was that there is no such $f$, but I wasn't sure how to show that.
Thanks in adavnce.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$

















    1












    $begingroup$


    Is there a partial recursive function $f$ that maps $e$ to the least element of $W_e$ if $W_eneq varnothing$?



    Can we apply the $mu$-operator (minimization) to a partially decidable predicate to get a partial recursive function (as in defining $f(x)=mu z(zin W_e)$ if $W_eneqvarnothing$ and undefined otherwise, since $zin W_e$ is partially decidable)?



    My guess was that there is no such $f$, but I wasn't sure how to show that.
    Thanks in adavnce.










    share|cite|improve this question









    $endgroup$















      1












      1








      1





      $begingroup$


      Is there a partial recursive function $f$ that maps $e$ to the least element of $W_e$ if $W_eneq varnothing$?



      Can we apply the $mu$-operator (minimization) to a partially decidable predicate to get a partial recursive function (as in defining $f(x)=mu z(zin W_e)$ if $W_eneqvarnothing$ and undefined otherwise, since $zin W_e$ is partially decidable)?



      My guess was that there is no such $f$, but I wasn't sure how to show that.
      Thanks in adavnce.










      share|cite|improve this question









      $endgroup$




      Is there a partial recursive function $f$ that maps $e$ to the least element of $W_e$ if $W_eneq varnothing$?



      Can we apply the $mu$-operator (minimization) to a partially decidable predicate to get a partial recursive function (as in defining $f(x)=mu z(zin W_e)$ if $W_eneqvarnothing$ and undefined otherwise, since $zin W_e$ is partially decidable)?



      My guess was that there is no such $f$, but I wasn't sure how to show that.
      Thanks in adavnce.







      logic computability






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked Dec 8 '18 at 20:26









      user500144user500144

      645




      645






















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          1












          $begingroup$

          Your intuition is right: there is no such function.



          We can see this in a couple different ways:




          • Contradiction: Suppose there were such an $f$. Then - given an arbitrary (infinite) c.e. set $A$ - we could compute the sequence $$min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)}), min(Asetminus{min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)})}), ...$$ by iteratively applying $f$. But this precisely enumerates $A$ in order, and so makes $A$ computable. Since there are non-computable sets, this can't happen.



          • Direct diagonalization: Given a computable function $f$, we can find an $e$ such that $(i)$ $2$ enters $W_e$ at stage $0$, $(ii)$ $1$ enters $W_e$ at stage $n+1$ iff $f(e)$ halts and outputs "$2$" at stage exactly $n$, and $(iii)$ no other numbers enter $W_e$ under any other circumstances. Then we get $min(W_e)=2$ iff $f(e)not=2$, so $f$ doesn't do what we want it to.




            • This fits into the "game picture" of c.e. sets: I pick a computable $f$, and you start building my $W_e$. You put $2$ into it, which forces me to eventually decide what $f(e)$ is; as soon as I do, if I say "$2$" then you put $1$ into my set, and if I say anything other than "$2$" you do nothing. Either way, you've defeated my purported $f$.




          I haven't provided full details of either case, but the idea should be clear. Filling in the details (of the first one, especially) is a good exercise.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            I haven't seen much of the "game" arguments, so could you explain what you mean by we "build $W_e$"? Isn't $W_e$ already determined for each $e$? Also, what do you mean by we can "find" $e$ such that 2 enters $W_e$ at stage 0... and so on?
            $endgroup$
            – user500144
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:02










          • $begingroup$
            @user500144 The two key ingredients here are Church's thesis and, more subtly, the recursion theorem. It's the latter which lets us seemingly "define $e$ while knowing already $e$."
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:05










          • $begingroup$
            Specifically, the argument has two pieces. Suppose $f$ has the property proposed. We begin with a Church's thesis argument: there is a total computable $h$ such that, for each $e$, we have $W_{h(e)}={1,2}$ if $f(e)downarrow=2$ and $W_{h(e)}={2}$ otherwise.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:16










          • $begingroup$
            (cont'd) The interesting step is applying the Recursion Theorem. Since $h$ is total computable, it has a fixed point - some $c$ such that $W_c=W_{h(c)}$. But then we have $W_{c}={1,2}$ if $f(c)downarrow=2$ and $W_c={2}$ otherwise - contradicting the assumption on $f$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:17










          • $begingroup$
            (contd) The recursion theorem aside (it is genuinely a technical result), all of this stuff becomes more intuitive once you think of c.e. sets as sets you can "enumerate effectively." E.g. intuitively we can effectively enumerate the theorems of a given (computably axiomatizable) theory: just search through all possible proofs and put sentences into the set we're building when we see them proved. This corresponds to the fact that the set of (Godel numbers of) theorems of a (computably axiomatizable) theory is c.e. So it's a useful intuitive device: if you can build it, it's $W_e$ for some $e$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:19











          Your Answer





          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          });
          });
          }, "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function() {
          var channelOptions = {
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          };
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
          createEditor();
          });
          }
          else {
          createEditor();
          }
          });

          function createEditor() {
          StackExchange.prepareEditor({
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader: {
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          },
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          });


          }
          });














          draft saved

          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3031600%2fis-there-a-partial-recursive-function-mapping-e-to-the-least-element-of-w-e%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown

























          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes








          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes









          1












          $begingroup$

          Your intuition is right: there is no such function.



          We can see this in a couple different ways:




          • Contradiction: Suppose there were such an $f$. Then - given an arbitrary (infinite) c.e. set $A$ - we could compute the sequence $$min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)}), min(Asetminus{min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)})}), ...$$ by iteratively applying $f$. But this precisely enumerates $A$ in order, and so makes $A$ computable. Since there are non-computable sets, this can't happen.



          • Direct diagonalization: Given a computable function $f$, we can find an $e$ such that $(i)$ $2$ enters $W_e$ at stage $0$, $(ii)$ $1$ enters $W_e$ at stage $n+1$ iff $f(e)$ halts and outputs "$2$" at stage exactly $n$, and $(iii)$ no other numbers enter $W_e$ under any other circumstances. Then we get $min(W_e)=2$ iff $f(e)not=2$, so $f$ doesn't do what we want it to.




            • This fits into the "game picture" of c.e. sets: I pick a computable $f$, and you start building my $W_e$. You put $2$ into it, which forces me to eventually decide what $f(e)$ is; as soon as I do, if I say "$2$" then you put $1$ into my set, and if I say anything other than "$2$" you do nothing. Either way, you've defeated my purported $f$.




          I haven't provided full details of either case, but the idea should be clear. Filling in the details (of the first one, especially) is a good exercise.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            I haven't seen much of the "game" arguments, so could you explain what you mean by we "build $W_e$"? Isn't $W_e$ already determined for each $e$? Also, what do you mean by we can "find" $e$ such that 2 enters $W_e$ at stage 0... and so on?
            $endgroup$
            – user500144
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:02










          • $begingroup$
            @user500144 The two key ingredients here are Church's thesis and, more subtly, the recursion theorem. It's the latter which lets us seemingly "define $e$ while knowing already $e$."
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:05










          • $begingroup$
            Specifically, the argument has two pieces. Suppose $f$ has the property proposed. We begin with a Church's thesis argument: there is a total computable $h$ such that, for each $e$, we have $W_{h(e)}={1,2}$ if $f(e)downarrow=2$ and $W_{h(e)}={2}$ otherwise.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:16










          • $begingroup$
            (cont'd) The interesting step is applying the Recursion Theorem. Since $h$ is total computable, it has a fixed point - some $c$ such that $W_c=W_{h(c)}$. But then we have $W_{c}={1,2}$ if $f(c)downarrow=2$ and $W_c={2}$ otherwise - contradicting the assumption on $f$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:17










          • $begingroup$
            (contd) The recursion theorem aside (it is genuinely a technical result), all of this stuff becomes more intuitive once you think of c.e. sets as sets you can "enumerate effectively." E.g. intuitively we can effectively enumerate the theorems of a given (computably axiomatizable) theory: just search through all possible proofs and put sentences into the set we're building when we see them proved. This corresponds to the fact that the set of (Godel numbers of) theorems of a (computably axiomatizable) theory is c.e. So it's a useful intuitive device: if you can build it, it's $W_e$ for some $e$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:19
















          1












          $begingroup$

          Your intuition is right: there is no such function.



          We can see this in a couple different ways:




          • Contradiction: Suppose there were such an $f$. Then - given an arbitrary (infinite) c.e. set $A$ - we could compute the sequence $$min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)}), min(Asetminus{min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)})}), ...$$ by iteratively applying $f$. But this precisely enumerates $A$ in order, and so makes $A$ computable. Since there are non-computable sets, this can't happen.



          • Direct diagonalization: Given a computable function $f$, we can find an $e$ such that $(i)$ $2$ enters $W_e$ at stage $0$, $(ii)$ $1$ enters $W_e$ at stage $n+1$ iff $f(e)$ halts and outputs "$2$" at stage exactly $n$, and $(iii)$ no other numbers enter $W_e$ under any other circumstances. Then we get $min(W_e)=2$ iff $f(e)not=2$, so $f$ doesn't do what we want it to.




            • This fits into the "game picture" of c.e. sets: I pick a computable $f$, and you start building my $W_e$. You put $2$ into it, which forces me to eventually decide what $f(e)$ is; as soon as I do, if I say "$2$" then you put $1$ into my set, and if I say anything other than "$2$" you do nothing. Either way, you've defeated my purported $f$.




          I haven't provided full details of either case, but the idea should be clear. Filling in the details (of the first one, especially) is a good exercise.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            I haven't seen much of the "game" arguments, so could you explain what you mean by we "build $W_e$"? Isn't $W_e$ already determined for each $e$? Also, what do you mean by we can "find" $e$ such that 2 enters $W_e$ at stage 0... and so on?
            $endgroup$
            – user500144
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:02










          • $begingroup$
            @user500144 The two key ingredients here are Church's thesis and, more subtly, the recursion theorem. It's the latter which lets us seemingly "define $e$ while knowing already $e$."
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:05










          • $begingroup$
            Specifically, the argument has two pieces. Suppose $f$ has the property proposed. We begin with a Church's thesis argument: there is a total computable $h$ such that, for each $e$, we have $W_{h(e)}={1,2}$ if $f(e)downarrow=2$ and $W_{h(e)}={2}$ otherwise.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:16










          • $begingroup$
            (cont'd) The interesting step is applying the Recursion Theorem. Since $h$ is total computable, it has a fixed point - some $c$ such that $W_c=W_{h(c)}$. But then we have $W_{c}={1,2}$ if $f(c)downarrow=2$ and $W_c={2}$ otherwise - contradicting the assumption on $f$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:17










          • $begingroup$
            (contd) The recursion theorem aside (it is genuinely a technical result), all of this stuff becomes more intuitive once you think of c.e. sets as sets you can "enumerate effectively." E.g. intuitively we can effectively enumerate the theorems of a given (computably axiomatizable) theory: just search through all possible proofs and put sentences into the set we're building when we see them proved. This corresponds to the fact that the set of (Godel numbers of) theorems of a (computably axiomatizable) theory is c.e. So it's a useful intuitive device: if you can build it, it's $W_e$ for some $e$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:19














          1












          1








          1





          $begingroup$

          Your intuition is right: there is no such function.



          We can see this in a couple different ways:




          • Contradiction: Suppose there were such an $f$. Then - given an arbitrary (infinite) c.e. set $A$ - we could compute the sequence $$min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)}), min(Asetminus{min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)})}), ...$$ by iteratively applying $f$. But this precisely enumerates $A$ in order, and so makes $A$ computable. Since there are non-computable sets, this can't happen.



          • Direct diagonalization: Given a computable function $f$, we can find an $e$ such that $(i)$ $2$ enters $W_e$ at stage $0$, $(ii)$ $1$ enters $W_e$ at stage $n+1$ iff $f(e)$ halts and outputs "$2$" at stage exactly $n$, and $(iii)$ no other numbers enter $W_e$ under any other circumstances. Then we get $min(W_e)=2$ iff $f(e)not=2$, so $f$ doesn't do what we want it to.




            • This fits into the "game picture" of c.e. sets: I pick a computable $f$, and you start building my $W_e$. You put $2$ into it, which forces me to eventually decide what $f(e)$ is; as soon as I do, if I say "$2$" then you put $1$ into my set, and if I say anything other than "$2$" you do nothing. Either way, you've defeated my purported $f$.




          I haven't provided full details of either case, but the idea should be clear. Filling in the details (of the first one, especially) is a good exercise.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          Your intuition is right: there is no such function.



          We can see this in a couple different ways:




          • Contradiction: Suppose there were such an $f$. Then - given an arbitrary (infinite) c.e. set $A$ - we could compute the sequence $$min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)}), min(Asetminus{min(A), min(Asetminus{min(A)})}), ...$$ by iteratively applying $f$. But this precisely enumerates $A$ in order, and so makes $A$ computable. Since there are non-computable sets, this can't happen.



          • Direct diagonalization: Given a computable function $f$, we can find an $e$ such that $(i)$ $2$ enters $W_e$ at stage $0$, $(ii)$ $1$ enters $W_e$ at stage $n+1$ iff $f(e)$ halts and outputs "$2$" at stage exactly $n$, and $(iii)$ no other numbers enter $W_e$ under any other circumstances. Then we get $min(W_e)=2$ iff $f(e)not=2$, so $f$ doesn't do what we want it to.




            • This fits into the "game picture" of c.e. sets: I pick a computable $f$, and you start building my $W_e$. You put $2$ into it, which forces me to eventually decide what $f(e)$ is; as soon as I do, if I say "$2$" then you put $1$ into my set, and if I say anything other than "$2$" you do nothing. Either way, you've defeated my purported $f$.




          I haven't provided full details of either case, but the idea should be clear. Filling in the details (of the first one, especially) is a good exercise.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Dec 8 '18 at 20:36









          Noah SchweberNoah Schweber

          127k10151290




          127k10151290












          • $begingroup$
            I haven't seen much of the "game" arguments, so could you explain what you mean by we "build $W_e$"? Isn't $W_e$ already determined for each $e$? Also, what do you mean by we can "find" $e$ such that 2 enters $W_e$ at stage 0... and so on?
            $endgroup$
            – user500144
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:02










          • $begingroup$
            @user500144 The two key ingredients here are Church's thesis and, more subtly, the recursion theorem. It's the latter which lets us seemingly "define $e$ while knowing already $e$."
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:05










          • $begingroup$
            Specifically, the argument has two pieces. Suppose $f$ has the property proposed. We begin with a Church's thesis argument: there is a total computable $h$ such that, for each $e$, we have $W_{h(e)}={1,2}$ if $f(e)downarrow=2$ and $W_{h(e)}={2}$ otherwise.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:16










          • $begingroup$
            (cont'd) The interesting step is applying the Recursion Theorem. Since $h$ is total computable, it has a fixed point - some $c$ such that $W_c=W_{h(c)}$. But then we have $W_{c}={1,2}$ if $f(c)downarrow=2$ and $W_c={2}$ otherwise - contradicting the assumption on $f$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:17










          • $begingroup$
            (contd) The recursion theorem aside (it is genuinely a technical result), all of this stuff becomes more intuitive once you think of c.e. sets as sets you can "enumerate effectively." E.g. intuitively we can effectively enumerate the theorems of a given (computably axiomatizable) theory: just search through all possible proofs and put sentences into the set we're building when we see them proved. This corresponds to the fact that the set of (Godel numbers of) theorems of a (computably axiomatizable) theory is c.e. So it's a useful intuitive device: if you can build it, it's $W_e$ for some $e$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:19


















          • $begingroup$
            I haven't seen much of the "game" arguments, so could you explain what you mean by we "build $W_e$"? Isn't $W_e$ already determined for each $e$? Also, what do you mean by we can "find" $e$ such that 2 enters $W_e$ at stage 0... and so on?
            $endgroup$
            – user500144
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:02










          • $begingroup$
            @user500144 The two key ingredients here are Church's thesis and, more subtly, the recursion theorem. It's the latter which lets us seemingly "define $e$ while knowing already $e$."
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:05










          • $begingroup$
            Specifically, the argument has two pieces. Suppose $f$ has the property proposed. We begin with a Church's thesis argument: there is a total computable $h$ such that, for each $e$, we have $W_{h(e)}={1,2}$ if $f(e)downarrow=2$ and $W_{h(e)}={2}$ otherwise.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:16










          • $begingroup$
            (cont'd) The interesting step is applying the Recursion Theorem. Since $h$ is total computable, it has a fixed point - some $c$ such that $W_c=W_{h(c)}$. But then we have $W_{c}={1,2}$ if $f(c)downarrow=2$ and $W_c={2}$ otherwise - contradicting the assumption on $f$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:17










          • $begingroup$
            (contd) The recursion theorem aside (it is genuinely a technical result), all of this stuff becomes more intuitive once you think of c.e. sets as sets you can "enumerate effectively." E.g. intuitively we can effectively enumerate the theorems of a given (computably axiomatizable) theory: just search through all possible proofs and put sentences into the set we're building when we see them proved. This corresponds to the fact that the set of (Godel numbers of) theorems of a (computably axiomatizable) theory is c.e. So it's a useful intuitive device: if you can build it, it's $W_e$ for some $e$.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 8 '18 at 21:19
















          $begingroup$
          I haven't seen much of the "game" arguments, so could you explain what you mean by we "build $W_e$"? Isn't $W_e$ already determined for each $e$? Also, what do you mean by we can "find" $e$ such that 2 enters $W_e$ at stage 0... and so on?
          $endgroup$
          – user500144
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:02




          $begingroup$
          I haven't seen much of the "game" arguments, so could you explain what you mean by we "build $W_e$"? Isn't $W_e$ already determined for each $e$? Also, what do you mean by we can "find" $e$ such that 2 enters $W_e$ at stage 0... and so on?
          $endgroup$
          – user500144
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:02












          $begingroup$
          @user500144 The two key ingredients here are Church's thesis and, more subtly, the recursion theorem. It's the latter which lets us seemingly "define $e$ while knowing already $e$."
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:05




          $begingroup$
          @user500144 The two key ingredients here are Church's thesis and, more subtly, the recursion theorem. It's the latter which lets us seemingly "define $e$ while knowing already $e$."
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:05












          $begingroup$
          Specifically, the argument has two pieces. Suppose $f$ has the property proposed. We begin with a Church's thesis argument: there is a total computable $h$ such that, for each $e$, we have $W_{h(e)}={1,2}$ if $f(e)downarrow=2$ and $W_{h(e)}={2}$ otherwise.
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:16




          $begingroup$
          Specifically, the argument has two pieces. Suppose $f$ has the property proposed. We begin with a Church's thesis argument: there is a total computable $h$ such that, for each $e$, we have $W_{h(e)}={1,2}$ if $f(e)downarrow=2$ and $W_{h(e)}={2}$ otherwise.
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:16












          $begingroup$
          (cont'd) The interesting step is applying the Recursion Theorem. Since $h$ is total computable, it has a fixed point - some $c$ such that $W_c=W_{h(c)}$. But then we have $W_{c}={1,2}$ if $f(c)downarrow=2$ and $W_c={2}$ otherwise - contradicting the assumption on $f$.
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:17




          $begingroup$
          (cont'd) The interesting step is applying the Recursion Theorem. Since $h$ is total computable, it has a fixed point - some $c$ such that $W_c=W_{h(c)}$. But then we have $W_{c}={1,2}$ if $f(c)downarrow=2$ and $W_c={2}$ otherwise - contradicting the assumption on $f$.
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:17












          $begingroup$
          (contd) The recursion theorem aside (it is genuinely a technical result), all of this stuff becomes more intuitive once you think of c.e. sets as sets you can "enumerate effectively." E.g. intuitively we can effectively enumerate the theorems of a given (computably axiomatizable) theory: just search through all possible proofs and put sentences into the set we're building when we see them proved. This corresponds to the fact that the set of (Godel numbers of) theorems of a (computably axiomatizable) theory is c.e. So it's a useful intuitive device: if you can build it, it's $W_e$ for some $e$.
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:19




          $begingroup$
          (contd) The recursion theorem aside (it is genuinely a technical result), all of this stuff becomes more intuitive once you think of c.e. sets as sets you can "enumerate effectively." E.g. intuitively we can effectively enumerate the theorems of a given (computably axiomatizable) theory: just search through all possible proofs and put sentences into the set we're building when we see them proved. This corresponds to the fact that the set of (Godel numbers of) theorems of a (computably axiomatizable) theory is c.e. So it's a useful intuitive device: if you can build it, it's $W_e$ for some $e$.
          $endgroup$
          – Noah Schweber
          Dec 8 '18 at 21:19


















          draft saved

          draft discarded




















































          Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


          • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

          But avoid



          • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

          • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


          Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


          To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3031600%2fis-there-a-partial-recursive-function-mapping-e-to-the-least-element-of-w-e%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown





















































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown

































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown







          Popular posts from this blog

          How to change which sound is reproduced for terminal bell?

          Title Spacing in Bjornstrup Chapter, Removing Chapter Number From Contents

          Can I use Tabulator js library in my java Spring + Thymeleaf project?