Importance of Axiom of Choice (or its weak form) in Real Analysis












2












$begingroup$


By Wikipedia article on Axiom of dependent choice, it is necessary to have it for development of real analysis. The ${mathsf {DC}}$ says:




Axiom (${mathsf{DC}}$). For any nonempty set $X$ and every entire binary relation $sim$ on $X$ there is a sequence $(x_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ s.t. $x_nsim x_{n+1}$ for all $ninmathbb{N}$.




I was looking for some examples of theorems in real analysis for which this axiom is necessary. Could this be an example?




Theorem: Number $alphainoverline{mathbb{R}}$ is a limit point of sequence $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ if and only if there exists a sub-sequence $(a_{k_n})_{ninmathbb{N}}$ such that $a_{k_n}rightarrow alpha$.



Proof. $Leftarrow:$ In every neighbourhood of $H_alpha$ lies infinitely many members of $(a_{k_n})$ thus infinitely many of $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow:$Assume neighbourhood $H_alpha(1)$. $alpha$ is a limit point, so there exists some $k_1$ s.t. $a_{k_1}in H_alpha(1)$. If $ninmathbb{N},n>1$, for neighbourhood $H_alpha(1/n)$ there exists $k_n>k_{n-1}$ satisfying $a_{k_n}in H_alpha(1/n)$. Such constructed sequence converges to $alpha$.




Now, this seems that we actually used the dependent choice in each step to construct the entire sequence. Without $mathsf{DC}$, we could only construct a finite one, am i correct?



Another example:




Theorem (Bolzano-Weierstrass): Every bounded sequence has a limit point $alphainmathbb{R}$.



Proof. Let $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ be bounded. Thus ${a_n}subseteq [b_1,c_1]$ where $[b_1,c_1]$ denotes real interval. Now we split this interval into two:
$$left[b_1,frac{b_1+c_1}{2}right],left[frac{b_1+c_1}{2},c_1right]$$
Atleast one of these contains infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Denote it by $[b_2,c_2]$. Following these steps, we construct a sequence of intervals $([b_n,c_n])$. For which $[b_k,c_k]subseteq[b_{k-1},c_{k-1}]$ for all $kinmathbb{N}$ and also their lengths converge to $0$. By nested intervals theorem (or axiom) there is a real number $x$ contained in each of $[b_n,c_n]$. By assumption, $[b_n,c_n]rightarrow 0$ thus for any $epsilon>0$ there is $n_0$ s.t. $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]<epsilon$. So for any neighbourhood $H_x$ there is such $n_{0}$ large enough such that $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]subseteq H_x$. But each of $[b_{n},c_{n}]$ for $n>n_0$ contains still infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$ thus $x$ is a limit point of $(a_n)$.




Again, we did use the dependent choice, didn't we? In each step, we are forced to add a new interval, because after split, in atleast one of them there must be infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Does the dependent choice here allow us to construct the entire sequence like this? Without it, we would be only able to construct a finite one



Let's give last example from ordering.




Theorem: Let $(S,<_S)$ be a poset. Then $(S,<_S)$ is well-ordered if and only if there is no infinite sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ s.t. $forall n inmathbb{N}: a_{n+1}<_Sa_n$



Proof $Leftarrow :$ (contrapositive). Assume $<_S$ is not well ordering. Thus there is a set $Tsubseteq S$ s.t. $T$ has no least element. Let $a_1in T$ be arbitrary. Because $a_1$ has no least element, there is some $xin T$ s.t. $x<_Sa_1$. Set $a_2=x$. Do the same process to construct monotone sequence $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow$ (contrapositive). Assume an infinite monotone sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ exists. Set $T={a_nmid ninmathbb{N}}$ (the elements of sequence $(a_n)$). $T$ obviously has no least element, thus $<_S$ is not well ordered.




Again, (in the $Leftarrow$ part) we were forced to have some $x$ below $a_1$. Without $mathsf{DC}$ we wouldn't be able to construct the entire sequence. Is that correct?



I am not looking for correctness of the proofs given above, they are correct . I am just looking for justification of my thoughts on this deeper leverl and if they're correct. On the other hand, let's make a big list of rather "trivial" statements which may seem to hide $mathsf{AC}$ or some of its weaker forms.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    For the 1st theorem, in the $implies$ part, for $ain Bbb R$, let $n_1$ be the least $n$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-1}$. Recursively let $n_{j+1}$ be the least $n>n_j$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-j-1}. $ This avoids the use of DC... Regarding big lists, perhaps you should ask for a reference to books about consequences and non-consequences of DC and AC.
    $endgroup$
    – DanielWainfleet
    Jan 1 at 19:15


















2












$begingroup$


By Wikipedia article on Axiom of dependent choice, it is necessary to have it for development of real analysis. The ${mathsf {DC}}$ says:




Axiom (${mathsf{DC}}$). For any nonempty set $X$ and every entire binary relation $sim$ on $X$ there is a sequence $(x_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ s.t. $x_nsim x_{n+1}$ for all $ninmathbb{N}$.




I was looking for some examples of theorems in real analysis for which this axiom is necessary. Could this be an example?




Theorem: Number $alphainoverline{mathbb{R}}$ is a limit point of sequence $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ if and only if there exists a sub-sequence $(a_{k_n})_{ninmathbb{N}}$ such that $a_{k_n}rightarrow alpha$.



Proof. $Leftarrow:$ In every neighbourhood of $H_alpha$ lies infinitely many members of $(a_{k_n})$ thus infinitely many of $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow:$Assume neighbourhood $H_alpha(1)$. $alpha$ is a limit point, so there exists some $k_1$ s.t. $a_{k_1}in H_alpha(1)$. If $ninmathbb{N},n>1$, for neighbourhood $H_alpha(1/n)$ there exists $k_n>k_{n-1}$ satisfying $a_{k_n}in H_alpha(1/n)$. Such constructed sequence converges to $alpha$.




Now, this seems that we actually used the dependent choice in each step to construct the entire sequence. Without $mathsf{DC}$, we could only construct a finite one, am i correct?



Another example:




Theorem (Bolzano-Weierstrass): Every bounded sequence has a limit point $alphainmathbb{R}$.



Proof. Let $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ be bounded. Thus ${a_n}subseteq [b_1,c_1]$ where $[b_1,c_1]$ denotes real interval. Now we split this interval into two:
$$left[b_1,frac{b_1+c_1}{2}right],left[frac{b_1+c_1}{2},c_1right]$$
Atleast one of these contains infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Denote it by $[b_2,c_2]$. Following these steps, we construct a sequence of intervals $([b_n,c_n])$. For which $[b_k,c_k]subseteq[b_{k-1},c_{k-1}]$ for all $kinmathbb{N}$ and also their lengths converge to $0$. By nested intervals theorem (or axiom) there is a real number $x$ contained in each of $[b_n,c_n]$. By assumption, $[b_n,c_n]rightarrow 0$ thus for any $epsilon>0$ there is $n_0$ s.t. $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]<epsilon$. So for any neighbourhood $H_x$ there is such $n_{0}$ large enough such that $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]subseteq H_x$. But each of $[b_{n},c_{n}]$ for $n>n_0$ contains still infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$ thus $x$ is a limit point of $(a_n)$.




Again, we did use the dependent choice, didn't we? In each step, we are forced to add a new interval, because after split, in atleast one of them there must be infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Does the dependent choice here allow us to construct the entire sequence like this? Without it, we would be only able to construct a finite one



Let's give last example from ordering.




Theorem: Let $(S,<_S)$ be a poset. Then $(S,<_S)$ is well-ordered if and only if there is no infinite sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ s.t. $forall n inmathbb{N}: a_{n+1}<_Sa_n$



Proof $Leftarrow :$ (contrapositive). Assume $<_S$ is not well ordering. Thus there is a set $Tsubseteq S$ s.t. $T$ has no least element. Let $a_1in T$ be arbitrary. Because $a_1$ has no least element, there is some $xin T$ s.t. $x<_Sa_1$. Set $a_2=x$. Do the same process to construct monotone sequence $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow$ (contrapositive). Assume an infinite monotone sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ exists. Set $T={a_nmid ninmathbb{N}}$ (the elements of sequence $(a_n)$). $T$ obviously has no least element, thus $<_S$ is not well ordered.




Again, (in the $Leftarrow$ part) we were forced to have some $x$ below $a_1$. Without $mathsf{DC}$ we wouldn't be able to construct the entire sequence. Is that correct?



I am not looking for correctness of the proofs given above, they are correct . I am just looking for justification of my thoughts on this deeper leverl and if they're correct. On the other hand, let's make a big list of rather "trivial" statements which may seem to hide $mathsf{AC}$ or some of its weaker forms.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    For the 1st theorem, in the $implies$ part, for $ain Bbb R$, let $n_1$ be the least $n$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-1}$. Recursively let $n_{j+1}$ be the least $n>n_j$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-j-1}. $ This avoids the use of DC... Regarding big lists, perhaps you should ask for a reference to books about consequences and non-consequences of DC and AC.
    $endgroup$
    – DanielWainfleet
    Jan 1 at 19:15
















2












2








2


2



$begingroup$


By Wikipedia article on Axiom of dependent choice, it is necessary to have it for development of real analysis. The ${mathsf {DC}}$ says:




Axiom (${mathsf{DC}}$). For any nonempty set $X$ and every entire binary relation $sim$ on $X$ there is a sequence $(x_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ s.t. $x_nsim x_{n+1}$ for all $ninmathbb{N}$.




I was looking for some examples of theorems in real analysis for which this axiom is necessary. Could this be an example?




Theorem: Number $alphainoverline{mathbb{R}}$ is a limit point of sequence $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ if and only if there exists a sub-sequence $(a_{k_n})_{ninmathbb{N}}$ such that $a_{k_n}rightarrow alpha$.



Proof. $Leftarrow:$ In every neighbourhood of $H_alpha$ lies infinitely many members of $(a_{k_n})$ thus infinitely many of $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow:$Assume neighbourhood $H_alpha(1)$. $alpha$ is a limit point, so there exists some $k_1$ s.t. $a_{k_1}in H_alpha(1)$. If $ninmathbb{N},n>1$, for neighbourhood $H_alpha(1/n)$ there exists $k_n>k_{n-1}$ satisfying $a_{k_n}in H_alpha(1/n)$. Such constructed sequence converges to $alpha$.




Now, this seems that we actually used the dependent choice in each step to construct the entire sequence. Without $mathsf{DC}$, we could only construct a finite one, am i correct?



Another example:




Theorem (Bolzano-Weierstrass): Every bounded sequence has a limit point $alphainmathbb{R}$.



Proof. Let $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ be bounded. Thus ${a_n}subseteq [b_1,c_1]$ where $[b_1,c_1]$ denotes real interval. Now we split this interval into two:
$$left[b_1,frac{b_1+c_1}{2}right],left[frac{b_1+c_1}{2},c_1right]$$
Atleast one of these contains infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Denote it by $[b_2,c_2]$. Following these steps, we construct a sequence of intervals $([b_n,c_n])$. For which $[b_k,c_k]subseteq[b_{k-1},c_{k-1}]$ for all $kinmathbb{N}$ and also their lengths converge to $0$. By nested intervals theorem (or axiom) there is a real number $x$ contained in each of $[b_n,c_n]$. By assumption, $[b_n,c_n]rightarrow 0$ thus for any $epsilon>0$ there is $n_0$ s.t. $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]<epsilon$. So for any neighbourhood $H_x$ there is such $n_{0}$ large enough such that $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]subseteq H_x$. But each of $[b_{n},c_{n}]$ for $n>n_0$ contains still infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$ thus $x$ is a limit point of $(a_n)$.




Again, we did use the dependent choice, didn't we? In each step, we are forced to add a new interval, because after split, in atleast one of them there must be infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Does the dependent choice here allow us to construct the entire sequence like this? Without it, we would be only able to construct a finite one



Let's give last example from ordering.




Theorem: Let $(S,<_S)$ be a poset. Then $(S,<_S)$ is well-ordered if and only if there is no infinite sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ s.t. $forall n inmathbb{N}: a_{n+1}<_Sa_n$



Proof $Leftarrow :$ (contrapositive). Assume $<_S$ is not well ordering. Thus there is a set $Tsubseteq S$ s.t. $T$ has no least element. Let $a_1in T$ be arbitrary. Because $a_1$ has no least element, there is some $xin T$ s.t. $x<_Sa_1$. Set $a_2=x$. Do the same process to construct monotone sequence $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow$ (contrapositive). Assume an infinite monotone sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ exists. Set $T={a_nmid ninmathbb{N}}$ (the elements of sequence $(a_n)$). $T$ obviously has no least element, thus $<_S$ is not well ordered.




Again, (in the $Leftarrow$ part) we were forced to have some $x$ below $a_1$. Without $mathsf{DC}$ we wouldn't be able to construct the entire sequence. Is that correct?



I am not looking for correctness of the proofs given above, they are correct . I am just looking for justification of my thoughts on this deeper leverl and if they're correct. On the other hand, let's make a big list of rather "trivial" statements which may seem to hide $mathsf{AC}$ or some of its weaker forms.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




By Wikipedia article on Axiom of dependent choice, it is necessary to have it for development of real analysis. The ${mathsf {DC}}$ says:




Axiom (${mathsf{DC}}$). For any nonempty set $X$ and every entire binary relation $sim$ on $X$ there is a sequence $(x_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ s.t. $x_nsim x_{n+1}$ for all $ninmathbb{N}$.




I was looking for some examples of theorems in real analysis for which this axiom is necessary. Could this be an example?




Theorem: Number $alphainoverline{mathbb{R}}$ is a limit point of sequence $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ if and only if there exists a sub-sequence $(a_{k_n})_{ninmathbb{N}}$ such that $a_{k_n}rightarrow alpha$.



Proof. $Leftarrow:$ In every neighbourhood of $H_alpha$ lies infinitely many members of $(a_{k_n})$ thus infinitely many of $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow:$Assume neighbourhood $H_alpha(1)$. $alpha$ is a limit point, so there exists some $k_1$ s.t. $a_{k_1}in H_alpha(1)$. If $ninmathbb{N},n>1$, for neighbourhood $H_alpha(1/n)$ there exists $k_n>k_{n-1}$ satisfying $a_{k_n}in H_alpha(1/n)$. Such constructed sequence converges to $alpha$.




Now, this seems that we actually used the dependent choice in each step to construct the entire sequence. Without $mathsf{DC}$, we could only construct a finite one, am i correct?



Another example:




Theorem (Bolzano-Weierstrass): Every bounded sequence has a limit point $alphainmathbb{R}$.



Proof. Let $(a_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ be bounded. Thus ${a_n}subseteq [b_1,c_1]$ where $[b_1,c_1]$ denotes real interval. Now we split this interval into two:
$$left[b_1,frac{b_1+c_1}{2}right],left[frac{b_1+c_1}{2},c_1right]$$
Atleast one of these contains infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Denote it by $[b_2,c_2]$. Following these steps, we construct a sequence of intervals $([b_n,c_n])$. For which $[b_k,c_k]subseteq[b_{k-1},c_{k-1}]$ for all $kinmathbb{N}$ and also their lengths converge to $0$. By nested intervals theorem (or axiom) there is a real number $x$ contained in each of $[b_n,c_n]$. By assumption, $[b_n,c_n]rightarrow 0$ thus for any $epsilon>0$ there is $n_0$ s.t. $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]<epsilon$. So for any neighbourhood $H_x$ there is such $n_{0}$ large enough such that $[b_{n_0},c_{n_0}]subseteq H_x$. But each of $[b_{n},c_{n}]$ for $n>n_0$ contains still infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$ thus $x$ is a limit point of $(a_n)$.




Again, we did use the dependent choice, didn't we? In each step, we are forced to add a new interval, because after split, in atleast one of them there must be infinitely many terms of $(a_n)$. Does the dependent choice here allow us to construct the entire sequence like this? Without it, we would be only able to construct a finite one



Let's give last example from ordering.




Theorem: Let $(S,<_S)$ be a poset. Then $(S,<_S)$ is well-ordered if and only if there is no infinite sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ s.t. $forall n inmathbb{N}: a_{n+1}<_Sa_n$



Proof $Leftarrow :$ (contrapositive). Assume $<_S$ is not well ordering. Thus there is a set $Tsubseteq S$ s.t. $T$ has no least element. Let $a_1in T$ be arbitrary. Because $a_1$ has no least element, there is some $xin T$ s.t. $x<_Sa_1$. Set $a_2=x$. Do the same process to construct monotone sequence $(a_n)$.



$Rightarrow$ (contrapositive). Assume an infinite monotone sequence $(a_n)$ in $S$ exists. Set $T={a_nmid ninmathbb{N}}$ (the elements of sequence $(a_n)$). $T$ obviously has no least element, thus $<_S$ is not well ordered.




Again, (in the $Leftarrow$ part) we were forced to have some $x$ below $a_1$. Without $mathsf{DC}$ we wouldn't be able to construct the entire sequence. Is that correct?



I am not looking for correctness of the proofs given above, they are correct . I am just looking for justification of my thoughts on this deeper leverl and if they're correct. On the other hand, let's make a big list of rather "trivial" statements which may seem to hide $mathsf{AC}$ or some of its weaker forms.







real-analysis proof-verification big-list big-picture






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Feb 12 at 15:27









mrtaurho

6,19771641




6,19771641










asked Jan 1 at 16:36









Michal DvořákMichal Dvořák

1,014416




1,014416












  • $begingroup$
    For the 1st theorem, in the $implies$ part, for $ain Bbb R$, let $n_1$ be the least $n$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-1}$. Recursively let $n_{j+1}$ be the least $n>n_j$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-j-1}. $ This avoids the use of DC... Regarding big lists, perhaps you should ask for a reference to books about consequences and non-consequences of DC and AC.
    $endgroup$
    – DanielWainfleet
    Jan 1 at 19:15




















  • $begingroup$
    For the 1st theorem, in the $implies$ part, for $ain Bbb R$, let $n_1$ be the least $n$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-1}$. Recursively let $n_{j+1}$ be the least $n>n_j$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-j-1}. $ This avoids the use of DC... Regarding big lists, perhaps you should ask for a reference to books about consequences and non-consequences of DC and AC.
    $endgroup$
    – DanielWainfleet
    Jan 1 at 19:15


















$begingroup$
For the 1st theorem, in the $implies$ part, for $ain Bbb R$, let $n_1$ be the least $n$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-1}$. Recursively let $n_{j+1}$ be the least $n>n_j$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-j-1}. $ This avoids the use of DC... Regarding big lists, perhaps you should ask for a reference to books about consequences and non-consequences of DC and AC.
$endgroup$
– DanielWainfleet
Jan 1 at 19:15






$begingroup$
For the 1st theorem, in the $implies$ part, for $ain Bbb R$, let $n_1$ be the least $n$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-1}$. Recursively let $n_{j+1}$ be the least $n>n_j$ such that $|a_n-a|<2^{-j-1}. $ This avoids the use of DC... Regarding big lists, perhaps you should ask for a reference to books about consequences and non-consequences of DC and AC.
$endgroup$
– DanielWainfleet
Jan 1 at 19:15












1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















6












$begingroup$

Typically, even DC is unnecessary for basic results in real analysis. It can usually be avoided by using the fact that "reals are countably approximable," in one of the two following forms:




  • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is second countable - it has as a base the set of all open intervals with rational endpoints.


  • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is separable - $mathbb{Q}$ is a countable dense set.



(Actually, what we're really using is well-orderable approximability - countability isn't relevant here, the point is that countable sets are well-orderable - but talking about countable approximability is probably more concrete at first.)



For example, here's how we can use the first point to give a choice-free proof of Bolzano-Weierstrass. Let $(I_i)_{iinmathbb{N}}$ enumerate the rational open intervals, and let $A=(a_j)_{jinmathbb{N}}$ be our sequence. For each $ninmathbb{N}$, let $k_n$ be the least natural number such that




  • $I_{k_n}$ contains infinitely many points from the sequence $A$, and


  • The diameter of $I_{k_n}$ is $<2^{-n}$.



Note that the existence of each $k_n$, and the sequence $(k_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$, is provable without using choice: the entire construction is explicit.



Now let $b_n$ be the right endpoint of $I_{k_n}$; the sequence $(b_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ is a Cauchy sequence, hence has a limit $beta$, and it's easy to check that $beta$ is in fact a limit point for the original sequence $A$.




Exercise: show that a similar argument proves the first theorem you mention without invoking choice.






On the other hand, in a "less-concrete" situation (= no longer "well-orderably-approximable"), we often do need some choice principle. For example, it's consistent with ZF (= set theory without choice) that there is a poset with no infinite descending sequence which however is not well-founded, so your third example really does constitute a necessary use of a choice principle. Functional analysis and point-set topology also provide examples, as do some seemingly-basic set theoretic questions about $mathbb{R}$ (for example, it's consistent with ZF that there is an infinite, Dedekind-finite set of real numbers).



But I would argue that there are vanishingly few examples in basic real analysis which actually need choice.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$














    Your Answer








    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3058630%2fimportance-of-axiom-of-choice-or-its-weak-form-in-real-analysis%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes








    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    6












    $begingroup$

    Typically, even DC is unnecessary for basic results in real analysis. It can usually be avoided by using the fact that "reals are countably approximable," in one of the two following forms:




    • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is second countable - it has as a base the set of all open intervals with rational endpoints.


    • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is separable - $mathbb{Q}$ is a countable dense set.



    (Actually, what we're really using is well-orderable approximability - countability isn't relevant here, the point is that countable sets are well-orderable - but talking about countable approximability is probably more concrete at first.)



    For example, here's how we can use the first point to give a choice-free proof of Bolzano-Weierstrass. Let $(I_i)_{iinmathbb{N}}$ enumerate the rational open intervals, and let $A=(a_j)_{jinmathbb{N}}$ be our sequence. For each $ninmathbb{N}$, let $k_n$ be the least natural number such that




    • $I_{k_n}$ contains infinitely many points from the sequence $A$, and


    • The diameter of $I_{k_n}$ is $<2^{-n}$.



    Note that the existence of each $k_n$, and the sequence $(k_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$, is provable without using choice: the entire construction is explicit.



    Now let $b_n$ be the right endpoint of $I_{k_n}$; the sequence $(b_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ is a Cauchy sequence, hence has a limit $beta$, and it's easy to check that $beta$ is in fact a limit point for the original sequence $A$.




    Exercise: show that a similar argument proves the first theorem you mention without invoking choice.






    On the other hand, in a "less-concrete" situation (= no longer "well-orderably-approximable"), we often do need some choice principle. For example, it's consistent with ZF (= set theory without choice) that there is a poset with no infinite descending sequence which however is not well-founded, so your third example really does constitute a necessary use of a choice principle. Functional analysis and point-set topology also provide examples, as do some seemingly-basic set theoretic questions about $mathbb{R}$ (for example, it's consistent with ZF that there is an infinite, Dedekind-finite set of real numbers).



    But I would argue that there are vanishingly few examples in basic real analysis which actually need choice.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      6












      $begingroup$

      Typically, even DC is unnecessary for basic results in real analysis. It can usually be avoided by using the fact that "reals are countably approximable," in one of the two following forms:




      • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is second countable - it has as a base the set of all open intervals with rational endpoints.


      • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is separable - $mathbb{Q}$ is a countable dense set.



      (Actually, what we're really using is well-orderable approximability - countability isn't relevant here, the point is that countable sets are well-orderable - but talking about countable approximability is probably more concrete at first.)



      For example, here's how we can use the first point to give a choice-free proof of Bolzano-Weierstrass. Let $(I_i)_{iinmathbb{N}}$ enumerate the rational open intervals, and let $A=(a_j)_{jinmathbb{N}}$ be our sequence. For each $ninmathbb{N}$, let $k_n$ be the least natural number such that




      • $I_{k_n}$ contains infinitely many points from the sequence $A$, and


      • The diameter of $I_{k_n}$ is $<2^{-n}$.



      Note that the existence of each $k_n$, and the sequence $(k_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$, is provable without using choice: the entire construction is explicit.



      Now let $b_n$ be the right endpoint of $I_{k_n}$; the sequence $(b_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ is a Cauchy sequence, hence has a limit $beta$, and it's easy to check that $beta$ is in fact a limit point for the original sequence $A$.




      Exercise: show that a similar argument proves the first theorem you mention without invoking choice.






      On the other hand, in a "less-concrete" situation (= no longer "well-orderably-approximable"), we often do need some choice principle. For example, it's consistent with ZF (= set theory without choice) that there is a poset with no infinite descending sequence which however is not well-founded, so your third example really does constitute a necessary use of a choice principle. Functional analysis and point-set topology also provide examples, as do some seemingly-basic set theoretic questions about $mathbb{R}$ (for example, it's consistent with ZF that there is an infinite, Dedekind-finite set of real numbers).



      But I would argue that there are vanishingly few examples in basic real analysis which actually need choice.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        6












        6








        6





        $begingroup$

        Typically, even DC is unnecessary for basic results in real analysis. It can usually be avoided by using the fact that "reals are countably approximable," in one of the two following forms:




        • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is second countable - it has as a base the set of all open intervals with rational endpoints.


        • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is separable - $mathbb{Q}$ is a countable dense set.



        (Actually, what we're really using is well-orderable approximability - countability isn't relevant here, the point is that countable sets are well-orderable - but talking about countable approximability is probably more concrete at first.)



        For example, here's how we can use the first point to give a choice-free proof of Bolzano-Weierstrass. Let $(I_i)_{iinmathbb{N}}$ enumerate the rational open intervals, and let $A=(a_j)_{jinmathbb{N}}$ be our sequence. For each $ninmathbb{N}$, let $k_n$ be the least natural number such that




        • $I_{k_n}$ contains infinitely many points from the sequence $A$, and


        • The diameter of $I_{k_n}$ is $<2^{-n}$.



        Note that the existence of each $k_n$, and the sequence $(k_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$, is provable without using choice: the entire construction is explicit.



        Now let $b_n$ be the right endpoint of $I_{k_n}$; the sequence $(b_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ is a Cauchy sequence, hence has a limit $beta$, and it's easy to check that $beta$ is in fact a limit point for the original sequence $A$.




        Exercise: show that a similar argument proves the first theorem you mention without invoking choice.






        On the other hand, in a "less-concrete" situation (= no longer "well-orderably-approximable"), we often do need some choice principle. For example, it's consistent with ZF (= set theory without choice) that there is a poset with no infinite descending sequence which however is not well-founded, so your third example really does constitute a necessary use of a choice principle. Functional analysis and point-set topology also provide examples, as do some seemingly-basic set theoretic questions about $mathbb{R}$ (for example, it's consistent with ZF that there is an infinite, Dedekind-finite set of real numbers).



        But I would argue that there are vanishingly few examples in basic real analysis which actually need choice.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        Typically, even DC is unnecessary for basic results in real analysis. It can usually be avoided by using the fact that "reals are countably approximable," in one of the two following forms:




        • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is second countable - it has as a base the set of all open intervals with rational endpoints.


        • The topology for $mathbb{R}$ is separable - $mathbb{Q}$ is a countable dense set.



        (Actually, what we're really using is well-orderable approximability - countability isn't relevant here, the point is that countable sets are well-orderable - but talking about countable approximability is probably more concrete at first.)



        For example, here's how we can use the first point to give a choice-free proof of Bolzano-Weierstrass. Let $(I_i)_{iinmathbb{N}}$ enumerate the rational open intervals, and let $A=(a_j)_{jinmathbb{N}}$ be our sequence. For each $ninmathbb{N}$, let $k_n$ be the least natural number such that




        • $I_{k_n}$ contains infinitely many points from the sequence $A$, and


        • The diameter of $I_{k_n}$ is $<2^{-n}$.



        Note that the existence of each $k_n$, and the sequence $(k_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$, is provable without using choice: the entire construction is explicit.



        Now let $b_n$ be the right endpoint of $I_{k_n}$; the sequence $(b_n)_{ninmathbb{N}}$ is a Cauchy sequence, hence has a limit $beta$, and it's easy to check that $beta$ is in fact a limit point for the original sequence $A$.




        Exercise: show that a similar argument proves the first theorem you mention without invoking choice.






        On the other hand, in a "less-concrete" situation (= no longer "well-orderably-approximable"), we often do need some choice principle. For example, it's consistent with ZF (= set theory without choice) that there is a poset with no infinite descending sequence which however is not well-founded, so your third example really does constitute a necessary use of a choice principle. Functional analysis and point-set topology also provide examples, as do some seemingly-basic set theoretic questions about $mathbb{R}$ (for example, it's consistent with ZF that there is an infinite, Dedekind-finite set of real numbers).



        But I would argue that there are vanishingly few examples in basic real analysis which actually need choice.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Jan 1 at 17:25









        Noah SchweberNoah Schweber

        129k10152294




        129k10152294






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3058630%2fimportance-of-axiom-of-choice-or-its-weak-form-in-real-analysis%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            How to change which sound is reproduced for terminal bell?

            Can I use Tabulator js library in my java Spring + Thymeleaf project?

            Title Spacing in Bjornstrup Chapter, Removing Chapter Number From Contents