Cantor's theorem (order theory)












2












$begingroup$


I will present a proof of Cantor's theorem (order theory), for which I will ask several questions.




Theorem (Cantor): Any $2$ countable linear dense orders with no end points are isomorphic.




Proof. Assume $(A,<_A),(B,<_B)$ satisfy premises. We construct isomorphisms $varphi_n$ iductively.



First, take any $ain A, bin B$ and set $varphi_1(a)=b$. We have (trivial) isomorphism $varphi_1:{a_1}rightarrow {b_1}$



Now, assume we have constructed isomorphisms up to $n$, for $ngeq1$. That is, we have isomorphism $varphi_n:{a_1,ldots,a_n}rightarrow {b_1,ldots,b_n}$. Now, pick an $ain Asetminus operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ (if this is nonempty, otherwise we are done and we have our desired isomorphism). Next, define
$$X={xinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid x<_Aa}$$
$$Y={yinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid a<_Ay}$$
That is, $X$ is the set of all elements below $a$ and $Y$ is the set of all elements above $a$, in some subset ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A$. Now, it cannot be the case that $X,Y$ are both empty, because $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ is nonempty and the ordering is linear (e.g. $a$ is comparable with atleast one element in $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$).



Assume now $X$ is empty, then minimum of $varphi_n(Y)$ exists (because $Y$ is finite), because $<_B$ has no endpoints, there is some $bin Bsetminusvarphi(Y)$ s.t. $b<min varphi_n(Y)$.



Simillarly, if $Y$ is empty, then maximum of $varphi_n(X)$ exists, so take some $b$ s.t. $max varphi_n (X)<b$.



If both $X,Y$ are nonempty, by simmilar arguments both $min varphi_n(Y)$ and varphi_n (X). Take some $b$ strictly in between these two (such $b$ exists, because $<_B$ is dense.



Now, set $varphi_{n+1}=varphi_ncup (a,b)$.



Then $$varphi:=bigcup_{ninmathbb{N}}varphi_n$$ is our desired isomorphism. Let's also check this really is an isomorphism. It is surely homomorphism, because of the construction, whenever $p<q$ then $varphi_n(p)<varphi_n(q)$. Injectivity follows. Surjectivity also holds, because in every step, we added exactly the tuple $(a,b)$ to $varphi_{n+1}$, so in any $bin{b_1,ldots,b_{n+1}}$ we find the pre-image in ${a_1,ldots,a_{n+1}}$.



My questions:




  1. Is the reasoning for surjectivity clear/valid/rigorous enough?


  2. Why can we say that if every "partial function" has a isomorphism property, then the final function $varphi$ (which is union of all of $varphi_n$'s) has still all the properties? It surely doesn't make sense to talk about something like "$lim_{ntoinfty} varphi_n=varphi$", does it?











share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$

















    2












    $begingroup$


    I will present a proof of Cantor's theorem (order theory), for which I will ask several questions.




    Theorem (Cantor): Any $2$ countable linear dense orders with no end points are isomorphic.




    Proof. Assume $(A,<_A),(B,<_B)$ satisfy premises. We construct isomorphisms $varphi_n$ iductively.



    First, take any $ain A, bin B$ and set $varphi_1(a)=b$. We have (trivial) isomorphism $varphi_1:{a_1}rightarrow {b_1}$



    Now, assume we have constructed isomorphisms up to $n$, for $ngeq1$. That is, we have isomorphism $varphi_n:{a_1,ldots,a_n}rightarrow {b_1,ldots,b_n}$. Now, pick an $ain Asetminus operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ (if this is nonempty, otherwise we are done and we have our desired isomorphism). Next, define
    $$X={xinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid x<_Aa}$$
    $$Y={yinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid a<_Ay}$$
    That is, $X$ is the set of all elements below $a$ and $Y$ is the set of all elements above $a$, in some subset ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A$. Now, it cannot be the case that $X,Y$ are both empty, because $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ is nonempty and the ordering is linear (e.g. $a$ is comparable with atleast one element in $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$).



    Assume now $X$ is empty, then minimum of $varphi_n(Y)$ exists (because $Y$ is finite), because $<_B$ has no endpoints, there is some $bin Bsetminusvarphi(Y)$ s.t. $b<min varphi_n(Y)$.



    Simillarly, if $Y$ is empty, then maximum of $varphi_n(X)$ exists, so take some $b$ s.t. $max varphi_n (X)<b$.



    If both $X,Y$ are nonempty, by simmilar arguments both $min varphi_n(Y)$ and varphi_n (X). Take some $b$ strictly in between these two (such $b$ exists, because $<_B$ is dense.



    Now, set $varphi_{n+1}=varphi_ncup (a,b)$.



    Then $$varphi:=bigcup_{ninmathbb{N}}varphi_n$$ is our desired isomorphism. Let's also check this really is an isomorphism. It is surely homomorphism, because of the construction, whenever $p<q$ then $varphi_n(p)<varphi_n(q)$. Injectivity follows. Surjectivity also holds, because in every step, we added exactly the tuple $(a,b)$ to $varphi_{n+1}$, so in any $bin{b_1,ldots,b_{n+1}}$ we find the pre-image in ${a_1,ldots,a_{n+1}}$.



    My questions:




    1. Is the reasoning for surjectivity clear/valid/rigorous enough?


    2. Why can we say that if every "partial function" has a isomorphism property, then the final function $varphi$ (which is union of all of $varphi_n$'s) has still all the properties? It surely doesn't make sense to talk about something like "$lim_{ntoinfty} varphi_n=varphi$", does it?











    share|cite|improve this question











    $endgroup$















      2












      2








      2





      $begingroup$


      I will present a proof of Cantor's theorem (order theory), for which I will ask several questions.




      Theorem (Cantor): Any $2$ countable linear dense orders with no end points are isomorphic.




      Proof. Assume $(A,<_A),(B,<_B)$ satisfy premises. We construct isomorphisms $varphi_n$ iductively.



      First, take any $ain A, bin B$ and set $varphi_1(a)=b$. We have (trivial) isomorphism $varphi_1:{a_1}rightarrow {b_1}$



      Now, assume we have constructed isomorphisms up to $n$, for $ngeq1$. That is, we have isomorphism $varphi_n:{a_1,ldots,a_n}rightarrow {b_1,ldots,b_n}$. Now, pick an $ain Asetminus operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ (if this is nonempty, otherwise we are done and we have our desired isomorphism). Next, define
      $$X={xinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid x<_Aa}$$
      $$Y={yinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid a<_Ay}$$
      That is, $X$ is the set of all elements below $a$ and $Y$ is the set of all elements above $a$, in some subset ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A$. Now, it cannot be the case that $X,Y$ are both empty, because $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ is nonempty and the ordering is linear (e.g. $a$ is comparable with atleast one element in $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$).



      Assume now $X$ is empty, then minimum of $varphi_n(Y)$ exists (because $Y$ is finite), because $<_B$ has no endpoints, there is some $bin Bsetminusvarphi(Y)$ s.t. $b<min varphi_n(Y)$.



      Simillarly, if $Y$ is empty, then maximum of $varphi_n(X)$ exists, so take some $b$ s.t. $max varphi_n (X)<b$.



      If both $X,Y$ are nonempty, by simmilar arguments both $min varphi_n(Y)$ and varphi_n (X). Take some $b$ strictly in between these two (such $b$ exists, because $<_B$ is dense.



      Now, set $varphi_{n+1}=varphi_ncup (a,b)$.



      Then $$varphi:=bigcup_{ninmathbb{N}}varphi_n$$ is our desired isomorphism. Let's also check this really is an isomorphism. It is surely homomorphism, because of the construction, whenever $p<q$ then $varphi_n(p)<varphi_n(q)$. Injectivity follows. Surjectivity also holds, because in every step, we added exactly the tuple $(a,b)$ to $varphi_{n+1}$, so in any $bin{b_1,ldots,b_{n+1}}$ we find the pre-image in ${a_1,ldots,a_{n+1}}$.



      My questions:




      1. Is the reasoning for surjectivity clear/valid/rigorous enough?


      2. Why can we say that if every "partial function" has a isomorphism property, then the final function $varphi$ (which is union of all of $varphi_n$'s) has still all the properties? It surely doesn't make sense to talk about something like "$lim_{ntoinfty} varphi_n=varphi$", does it?











      share|cite|improve this question











      $endgroup$




      I will present a proof of Cantor's theorem (order theory), for which I will ask several questions.




      Theorem (Cantor): Any $2$ countable linear dense orders with no end points are isomorphic.




      Proof. Assume $(A,<_A),(B,<_B)$ satisfy premises. We construct isomorphisms $varphi_n$ iductively.



      First, take any $ain A, bin B$ and set $varphi_1(a)=b$. We have (trivial) isomorphism $varphi_1:{a_1}rightarrow {b_1}$



      Now, assume we have constructed isomorphisms up to $n$, for $ngeq1$. That is, we have isomorphism $varphi_n:{a_1,ldots,a_n}rightarrow {b_1,ldots,b_n}$. Now, pick an $ain Asetminus operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ (if this is nonempty, otherwise we are done and we have our desired isomorphism). Next, define
      $$X={xinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid x<_Aa}$$
      $$Y={yinoperatorname{dom}(varphi_n)mid a<_Ay}$$
      That is, $X$ is the set of all elements below $a$ and $Y$ is the set of all elements above $a$, in some subset ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A$. Now, it cannot be the case that $X,Y$ are both empty, because $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$ is nonempty and the ordering is linear (e.g. $a$ is comparable with atleast one element in $operatorname{dom}(varphi_n)$).



      Assume now $X$ is empty, then minimum of $varphi_n(Y)$ exists (because $Y$ is finite), because $<_B$ has no endpoints, there is some $bin Bsetminusvarphi(Y)$ s.t. $b<min varphi_n(Y)$.



      Simillarly, if $Y$ is empty, then maximum of $varphi_n(X)$ exists, so take some $b$ s.t. $max varphi_n (X)<b$.



      If both $X,Y$ are nonempty, by simmilar arguments both $min varphi_n(Y)$ and varphi_n (X). Take some $b$ strictly in between these two (such $b$ exists, because $<_B$ is dense.



      Now, set $varphi_{n+1}=varphi_ncup (a,b)$.



      Then $$varphi:=bigcup_{ninmathbb{N}}varphi_n$$ is our desired isomorphism. Let's also check this really is an isomorphism. It is surely homomorphism, because of the construction, whenever $p<q$ then $varphi_n(p)<varphi_n(q)$. Injectivity follows. Surjectivity also holds, because in every step, we added exactly the tuple $(a,b)$ to $varphi_{n+1}$, so in any $bin{b_1,ldots,b_{n+1}}$ we find the pre-image in ${a_1,ldots,a_{n+1}}$.



      My questions:




      1. Is the reasoning for surjectivity clear/valid/rigorous enough?


      2. Why can we say that if every "partial function" has a isomorphism property, then the final function $varphi$ (which is union of all of $varphi_n$'s) has still all the properties? It surely doesn't make sense to talk about something like "$lim_{ntoinfty} varphi_n=varphi$", does it?








      proof-writing proof-explanation order-theory






      share|cite|improve this question















      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited Dec 3 '18 at 23:31







      Michal Dvořák

















      asked Dec 3 '18 at 22:00









      Michal DvořákMichal Dvořák

      966416




      966416






















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          1












          $begingroup$


          1. No (it looks like a misquoted proof). With the presented construction, one can only conclude that $varphi$ is an isomorphism of some subsets of $A$ and $B$. See below for a corrected construction.
            $newcommand{dom}{operatorname{dom}} newcommand{im}{operatorname{im}}$

          2. This is easy. Say, if $a,bindomvarphi=cup_{ninmathbb{N}}domvarphi_n$ and $a <_A b$, there is $ninmathbb{N}$ such that $a,bindomvarphi_n$, therefore $varphi(a) = varphi_n(a) <_B varphi_n(b) = varphi(b)$.


          The proofs I've seen proceed as follows. Let $A={a_1,a_2,ldots}$ and $B={b_1,b_2,ldots}$. We build isomorphisms $varphi_n : A_n to B_n$, but now such that ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A_n$ and ${b_1,ldots,b_n}subseteq B_n$.



          Put $varphi_1={(a_1,b_1)}$. Suppose $varphi_{n-1}$ is built. If $a_nin A_{n-1}$ let $b=varphi_{n-1}(a_n)$; otherwise take $bin Bsetminus B_{n-1}$ so that $b <_B varphi_{n-1}(c) iff a_n <_A c$ holds for all $cin A_{n-1}$ (with existence justified exactly the way you did).



          Now (we are in the middle of a step) let $psi=varphi_{n-1}cup{(a_n,b)}$ and, similarly, if $b_ninimpsi$ we let $a=psi^{-1}(b_n)$, otherwise we take $ain Asetminus A_{n-1}$ so that $a <_A c iff b_n <_B psi(c)$ holds for $cindompsi$; finally, we put $varphi_n=psicup{(a,b_n)}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            So, in every step, we construct two new pairs for the function, yes? Otherwise we are not able to prove that it really is an isomorphism, is that correct?
            $endgroup$
            – Michal Dvořák
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:48












          • $begingroup$
            Yes (or, alternatively, we handle $A$ on odd steps and $B$ on even steps). We cover each element of $A$ and $B$, not just any.
            $endgroup$
            – metamorphy
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:51











          Your Answer





          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          });
          });
          }, "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function() {
          var channelOptions = {
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          };
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
          createEditor();
          });
          }
          else {
          createEditor();
          }
          });

          function createEditor() {
          StackExchange.prepareEditor({
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader: {
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          },
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          });


          }
          });














          draft saved

          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3024746%2fcantors-theorem-order-theory%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown

























          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes








          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes









          1












          $begingroup$


          1. No (it looks like a misquoted proof). With the presented construction, one can only conclude that $varphi$ is an isomorphism of some subsets of $A$ and $B$. See below for a corrected construction.
            $newcommand{dom}{operatorname{dom}} newcommand{im}{operatorname{im}}$

          2. This is easy. Say, if $a,bindomvarphi=cup_{ninmathbb{N}}domvarphi_n$ and $a <_A b$, there is $ninmathbb{N}$ such that $a,bindomvarphi_n$, therefore $varphi(a) = varphi_n(a) <_B varphi_n(b) = varphi(b)$.


          The proofs I've seen proceed as follows. Let $A={a_1,a_2,ldots}$ and $B={b_1,b_2,ldots}$. We build isomorphisms $varphi_n : A_n to B_n$, but now such that ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A_n$ and ${b_1,ldots,b_n}subseteq B_n$.



          Put $varphi_1={(a_1,b_1)}$. Suppose $varphi_{n-1}$ is built. If $a_nin A_{n-1}$ let $b=varphi_{n-1}(a_n)$; otherwise take $bin Bsetminus B_{n-1}$ so that $b <_B varphi_{n-1}(c) iff a_n <_A c$ holds for all $cin A_{n-1}$ (with existence justified exactly the way you did).



          Now (we are in the middle of a step) let $psi=varphi_{n-1}cup{(a_n,b)}$ and, similarly, if $b_ninimpsi$ we let $a=psi^{-1}(b_n)$, otherwise we take $ain Asetminus A_{n-1}$ so that $a <_A c iff b_n <_B psi(c)$ holds for $cindompsi$; finally, we put $varphi_n=psicup{(a,b_n)}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            So, in every step, we construct two new pairs for the function, yes? Otherwise we are not able to prove that it really is an isomorphism, is that correct?
            $endgroup$
            – Michal Dvořák
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:48












          • $begingroup$
            Yes (or, alternatively, we handle $A$ on odd steps and $B$ on even steps). We cover each element of $A$ and $B$, not just any.
            $endgroup$
            – metamorphy
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:51
















          1












          $begingroup$


          1. No (it looks like a misquoted proof). With the presented construction, one can only conclude that $varphi$ is an isomorphism of some subsets of $A$ and $B$. See below for a corrected construction.
            $newcommand{dom}{operatorname{dom}} newcommand{im}{operatorname{im}}$

          2. This is easy. Say, if $a,bindomvarphi=cup_{ninmathbb{N}}domvarphi_n$ and $a <_A b$, there is $ninmathbb{N}$ such that $a,bindomvarphi_n$, therefore $varphi(a) = varphi_n(a) <_B varphi_n(b) = varphi(b)$.


          The proofs I've seen proceed as follows. Let $A={a_1,a_2,ldots}$ and $B={b_1,b_2,ldots}$. We build isomorphisms $varphi_n : A_n to B_n$, but now such that ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A_n$ and ${b_1,ldots,b_n}subseteq B_n$.



          Put $varphi_1={(a_1,b_1)}$. Suppose $varphi_{n-1}$ is built. If $a_nin A_{n-1}$ let $b=varphi_{n-1}(a_n)$; otherwise take $bin Bsetminus B_{n-1}$ so that $b <_B varphi_{n-1}(c) iff a_n <_A c$ holds for all $cin A_{n-1}$ (with existence justified exactly the way you did).



          Now (we are in the middle of a step) let $psi=varphi_{n-1}cup{(a_n,b)}$ and, similarly, if $b_ninimpsi$ we let $a=psi^{-1}(b_n)$, otherwise we take $ain Asetminus A_{n-1}$ so that $a <_A c iff b_n <_B psi(c)$ holds for $cindompsi$; finally, we put $varphi_n=psicup{(a,b_n)}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            So, in every step, we construct two new pairs for the function, yes? Otherwise we are not able to prove that it really is an isomorphism, is that correct?
            $endgroup$
            – Michal Dvořák
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:48












          • $begingroup$
            Yes (or, alternatively, we handle $A$ on odd steps and $B$ on even steps). We cover each element of $A$ and $B$, not just any.
            $endgroup$
            – metamorphy
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:51














          1












          1








          1





          $begingroup$


          1. No (it looks like a misquoted proof). With the presented construction, one can only conclude that $varphi$ is an isomorphism of some subsets of $A$ and $B$. See below for a corrected construction.
            $newcommand{dom}{operatorname{dom}} newcommand{im}{operatorname{im}}$

          2. This is easy. Say, if $a,bindomvarphi=cup_{ninmathbb{N}}domvarphi_n$ and $a <_A b$, there is $ninmathbb{N}$ such that $a,bindomvarphi_n$, therefore $varphi(a) = varphi_n(a) <_B varphi_n(b) = varphi(b)$.


          The proofs I've seen proceed as follows. Let $A={a_1,a_2,ldots}$ and $B={b_1,b_2,ldots}$. We build isomorphisms $varphi_n : A_n to B_n$, but now such that ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A_n$ and ${b_1,ldots,b_n}subseteq B_n$.



          Put $varphi_1={(a_1,b_1)}$. Suppose $varphi_{n-1}$ is built. If $a_nin A_{n-1}$ let $b=varphi_{n-1}(a_n)$; otherwise take $bin Bsetminus B_{n-1}$ so that $b <_B varphi_{n-1}(c) iff a_n <_A c$ holds for all $cin A_{n-1}$ (with existence justified exactly the way you did).



          Now (we are in the middle of a step) let $psi=varphi_{n-1}cup{(a_n,b)}$ and, similarly, if $b_ninimpsi$ we let $a=psi^{-1}(b_n)$, otherwise we take $ain Asetminus A_{n-1}$ so that $a <_A c iff b_n <_B psi(c)$ holds for $cindompsi$; finally, we put $varphi_n=psicup{(a,b_n)}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$




          1. No (it looks like a misquoted proof). With the presented construction, one can only conclude that $varphi$ is an isomorphism of some subsets of $A$ and $B$. See below for a corrected construction.
            $newcommand{dom}{operatorname{dom}} newcommand{im}{operatorname{im}}$

          2. This is easy. Say, if $a,bindomvarphi=cup_{ninmathbb{N}}domvarphi_n$ and $a <_A b$, there is $ninmathbb{N}$ such that $a,bindomvarphi_n$, therefore $varphi(a) = varphi_n(a) <_B varphi_n(b) = varphi(b)$.


          The proofs I've seen proceed as follows. Let $A={a_1,a_2,ldots}$ and $B={b_1,b_2,ldots}$. We build isomorphisms $varphi_n : A_n to B_n$, but now such that ${a_1,ldots,a_n}subseteq A_n$ and ${b_1,ldots,b_n}subseteq B_n$.



          Put $varphi_1={(a_1,b_1)}$. Suppose $varphi_{n-1}$ is built. If $a_nin A_{n-1}$ let $b=varphi_{n-1}(a_n)$; otherwise take $bin Bsetminus B_{n-1}$ so that $b <_B varphi_{n-1}(c) iff a_n <_A c$ holds for all $cin A_{n-1}$ (with existence justified exactly the way you did).



          Now (we are in the middle of a step) let $psi=varphi_{n-1}cup{(a_n,b)}$ and, similarly, if $b_ninimpsi$ we let $a=psi^{-1}(b_n)$, otherwise we take $ain Asetminus A_{n-1}$ so that $a <_A c iff b_n <_B psi(c)$ holds for $cindompsi$; finally, we put $varphi_n=psicup{(a,b_n)}$.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited Dec 22 '18 at 16:17

























          answered Dec 3 '18 at 23:44









          metamorphymetamorphy

          3,6921621




          3,6921621












          • $begingroup$
            So, in every step, we construct two new pairs for the function, yes? Otherwise we are not able to prove that it really is an isomorphism, is that correct?
            $endgroup$
            – Michal Dvořák
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:48












          • $begingroup$
            Yes (or, alternatively, we handle $A$ on odd steps and $B$ on even steps). We cover each element of $A$ and $B$, not just any.
            $endgroup$
            – metamorphy
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:51


















          • $begingroup$
            So, in every step, we construct two new pairs for the function, yes? Otherwise we are not able to prove that it really is an isomorphism, is that correct?
            $endgroup$
            – Michal Dvořák
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:48












          • $begingroup$
            Yes (or, alternatively, we handle $A$ on odd steps and $B$ on even steps). We cover each element of $A$ and $B$, not just any.
            $endgroup$
            – metamorphy
            Dec 3 '18 at 23:51
















          $begingroup$
          So, in every step, we construct two new pairs for the function, yes? Otherwise we are not able to prove that it really is an isomorphism, is that correct?
          $endgroup$
          – Michal Dvořák
          Dec 3 '18 at 23:48






          $begingroup$
          So, in every step, we construct two new pairs for the function, yes? Otherwise we are not able to prove that it really is an isomorphism, is that correct?
          $endgroup$
          – Michal Dvořák
          Dec 3 '18 at 23:48














          $begingroup$
          Yes (or, alternatively, we handle $A$ on odd steps and $B$ on even steps). We cover each element of $A$ and $B$, not just any.
          $endgroup$
          – metamorphy
          Dec 3 '18 at 23:51




          $begingroup$
          Yes (or, alternatively, we handle $A$ on odd steps and $B$ on even steps). We cover each element of $A$ and $B$, not just any.
          $endgroup$
          – metamorphy
          Dec 3 '18 at 23:51


















          draft saved

          draft discarded




















































          Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


          • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

          But avoid



          • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

          • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


          Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


          To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3024746%2fcantors-theorem-order-theory%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown





















































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown

































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown







          Popular posts from this blog

          Biblatex bibliography style without URLs when DOI exists (in Overleaf with Zotero bibliography)

          ComboBox Display Member on multiple fields

          Is it possible to collect Nectar points via Trainline?