How do I prove $p,¬p ⊢q$ with logic? [closed]












-1












$begingroup$


The answer mentions it is a tautology but does not explain the procedure.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$



closed as off-topic by user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson Mar 25 at 13:26


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.
















  • $begingroup$
    It is not a tautology; it is a valid propositional argument (or tautological argument).
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:20












  • $begingroup$
    You can use the Truth Tables method to check it.
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:21
















-1












$begingroup$


The answer mentions it is a tautology but does not explain the procedure.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$



closed as off-topic by user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson Mar 25 at 13:26


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.
















  • $begingroup$
    It is not a tautology; it is a valid propositional argument (or tautological argument).
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:20












  • $begingroup$
    You can use the Truth Tables method to check it.
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:21














-1












-1








-1





$begingroup$


The answer mentions it is a tautology but does not explain the procedure.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




The answer mentions it is a tautology but does not explain the procedure.







logic






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Dec 27 '18 at 2:20









Key Flex

8,58171233




8,58171233










asked Dec 27 '18 at 1:06









AlexAlex

51




51




closed as off-topic by user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson Mar 25 at 13:26


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.







closed as off-topic by user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson Mar 25 at 13:26


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – user21820, Saad, José Carlos Santos, RRL, Xander Henderson

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.












  • $begingroup$
    It is not a tautology; it is a valid propositional argument (or tautological argument).
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:20












  • $begingroup$
    You can use the Truth Tables method to check it.
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:21


















  • $begingroup$
    It is not a tautology; it is a valid propositional argument (or tautological argument).
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:20












  • $begingroup$
    You can use the Truth Tables method to check it.
    $endgroup$
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    Dec 27 '18 at 9:21
















$begingroup$
It is not a tautology; it is a valid propositional argument (or tautological argument).
$endgroup$
– Mauro ALLEGRANZA
Dec 27 '18 at 9:20






$begingroup$
It is not a tautology; it is a valid propositional argument (or tautological argument).
$endgroup$
– Mauro ALLEGRANZA
Dec 27 '18 at 9:20














$begingroup$
You can use the Truth Tables method to check it.
$endgroup$
– Mauro ALLEGRANZA
Dec 27 '18 at 9:21




$begingroup$
You can use the Truth Tables method to check it.
$endgroup$
– Mauro ALLEGRANZA
Dec 27 '18 at 9:21










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















1












$begingroup$

So, not every logic does this! (There are many different logics based on the rules that you are allowed to use to infer things.)



In particular, this is called the principle of explosion and the logics which reject it are called paraconsistent logics. Usually to make normal logic into a paraconsistent system you delete one of the following rules:




  1. If we have concluded $X$ then we can conclude, for any $Y$, $X vee Y$, which you can read as "either $X$ or $Y$ (or both)."


  2. If we have concluded both $X vee Y$ and $neg X$, then we can conclude $Y$.



If you have both of these rules in your arsenal then it is easy to see why knowing both $P$ and $neg P$ would entail any $Q$, just first use $P$ to conclude $P vee Q$ and then use that plus $neg P$ to entail $Q$.



Since these are standard rules, dropping them from your logic results in a weaker logic: it doesn't prove any new things, it just fails to prove some existing things that the stronger logic has no problem with.



One motivation why some mathematicians (and philosophers etc.) wish to do this sort of thing has to do with the very shape of this claim "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q.$" Classical logic is very happy to rewrite $X to Y$ as $neg X vee Y$ in a way that enables vacuous consistency, for example I might say "if it is raining in Ithaca right now then the President of the United States is a gerbil!" and that is a completely true statement because it happens to be snowing, not raining, in Ithaca right now. But for a lot of folks this doesn't "smell right" because these things are not related to each other, and I want to say that I should only be able to phrase $X to Y$ when there is some sort of meaningful connection called "relevance" between $X$ and $Y$. Well the problem with "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q$" is precisely that the "for all $Q$" must include statements which are not relevant to either $P$ or $neg P$ and therefore cannot be relevant to $P wedge neg P$.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    0












    $begingroup$

    Think about it this way:



    If we have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash p$ and we also have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash neg p$ (we know we have these because we can assume anything that's inside the premise set)
    then we can move the negation of one of the things inside our premise set onto the right side (since we had a contradiction). It doesn't matter which thing we move outside the premise set, so we can choose to move the $neg q$ outside. This means that



    {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg neg q$



    {$p,neg p$} $vdash q$



    Notice that we could have actually used just $q$ in our premise set instead of $neg q$, so this means that

    {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg q$



    In fact, {$p,neg p$} can imply anything.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Please ask if you have any questions
      $endgroup$
      – Riley H
      Dec 27 '18 at 1:40






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Sorry if this is a basic question: why does a contradiction allow us to move something from the premise to the right side?
      $endgroup$
      – Alex
      Dec 27 '18 at 1:58






    • 2




      $begingroup$
      @Alex the way I think of it is that if you arrive at a contradiction, then something in your premise set must be wrong. However, you don't necessarily know what is wrong, so you can move the negation of one thing (in the premise set) onto the right side. This may seem a little cheaty, but we aren't breaking any rules as if we were to move the wrong assumption onto the right side and negate it (when I say wrong I mean it isn't helping our proof), then we will just end up with a statement that doesn't help us, but is still logically correct
      $endgroup$
      – Riley H
      Dec 27 '18 at 2:05






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @Alex I found a much better way of seeing this on wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion
      $endgroup$
      – Riley H
      Dec 27 '18 at 2:06



















    0












    $begingroup$

    To prove $Aimplies [neg A implies B]$ you need only the following elementary methods and rules of natural deduction:





    1. $implies$-Introduction (Conlusion, direct proof)


    2. $neg$-Introduction (Conclusion, proof by contradiction)


    3. $land$-Introduction (Join)


    4. $negneg$-Elimination (Rem DNeg)


    In DC Proof, for example (user comments in blue font):



    enter image description here






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$




















      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes








      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      1












      $begingroup$

      So, not every logic does this! (There are many different logics based on the rules that you are allowed to use to infer things.)



      In particular, this is called the principle of explosion and the logics which reject it are called paraconsistent logics. Usually to make normal logic into a paraconsistent system you delete one of the following rules:




      1. If we have concluded $X$ then we can conclude, for any $Y$, $X vee Y$, which you can read as "either $X$ or $Y$ (or both)."


      2. If we have concluded both $X vee Y$ and $neg X$, then we can conclude $Y$.



      If you have both of these rules in your arsenal then it is easy to see why knowing both $P$ and $neg P$ would entail any $Q$, just first use $P$ to conclude $P vee Q$ and then use that plus $neg P$ to entail $Q$.



      Since these are standard rules, dropping them from your logic results in a weaker logic: it doesn't prove any new things, it just fails to prove some existing things that the stronger logic has no problem with.



      One motivation why some mathematicians (and philosophers etc.) wish to do this sort of thing has to do with the very shape of this claim "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q.$" Classical logic is very happy to rewrite $X to Y$ as $neg X vee Y$ in a way that enables vacuous consistency, for example I might say "if it is raining in Ithaca right now then the President of the United States is a gerbil!" and that is a completely true statement because it happens to be snowing, not raining, in Ithaca right now. But for a lot of folks this doesn't "smell right" because these things are not related to each other, and I want to say that I should only be able to phrase $X to Y$ when there is some sort of meaningful connection called "relevance" between $X$ and $Y$. Well the problem with "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q$" is precisely that the "for all $Q$" must include statements which are not relevant to either $P$ or $neg P$ and therefore cannot be relevant to $P wedge neg P$.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$


















        1












        $begingroup$

        So, not every logic does this! (There are many different logics based on the rules that you are allowed to use to infer things.)



        In particular, this is called the principle of explosion and the logics which reject it are called paraconsistent logics. Usually to make normal logic into a paraconsistent system you delete one of the following rules:




        1. If we have concluded $X$ then we can conclude, for any $Y$, $X vee Y$, which you can read as "either $X$ or $Y$ (or both)."


        2. If we have concluded both $X vee Y$ and $neg X$, then we can conclude $Y$.



        If you have both of these rules in your arsenal then it is easy to see why knowing both $P$ and $neg P$ would entail any $Q$, just first use $P$ to conclude $P vee Q$ and then use that plus $neg P$ to entail $Q$.



        Since these are standard rules, dropping them from your logic results in a weaker logic: it doesn't prove any new things, it just fails to prove some existing things that the stronger logic has no problem with.



        One motivation why some mathematicians (and philosophers etc.) wish to do this sort of thing has to do with the very shape of this claim "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q.$" Classical logic is very happy to rewrite $X to Y$ as $neg X vee Y$ in a way that enables vacuous consistency, for example I might say "if it is raining in Ithaca right now then the President of the United States is a gerbil!" and that is a completely true statement because it happens to be snowing, not raining, in Ithaca right now. But for a lot of folks this doesn't "smell right" because these things are not related to each other, and I want to say that I should only be able to phrase $X to Y$ when there is some sort of meaningful connection called "relevance" between $X$ and $Y$. Well the problem with "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q$" is precisely that the "for all $Q$" must include statements which are not relevant to either $P$ or $neg P$ and therefore cannot be relevant to $P wedge neg P$.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$
















          1












          1








          1





          $begingroup$

          So, not every logic does this! (There are many different logics based on the rules that you are allowed to use to infer things.)



          In particular, this is called the principle of explosion and the logics which reject it are called paraconsistent logics. Usually to make normal logic into a paraconsistent system you delete one of the following rules:




          1. If we have concluded $X$ then we can conclude, for any $Y$, $X vee Y$, which you can read as "either $X$ or $Y$ (or both)."


          2. If we have concluded both $X vee Y$ and $neg X$, then we can conclude $Y$.



          If you have both of these rules in your arsenal then it is easy to see why knowing both $P$ and $neg P$ would entail any $Q$, just first use $P$ to conclude $P vee Q$ and then use that plus $neg P$ to entail $Q$.



          Since these are standard rules, dropping them from your logic results in a weaker logic: it doesn't prove any new things, it just fails to prove some existing things that the stronger logic has no problem with.



          One motivation why some mathematicians (and philosophers etc.) wish to do this sort of thing has to do with the very shape of this claim "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q.$" Classical logic is very happy to rewrite $X to Y$ as $neg X vee Y$ in a way that enables vacuous consistency, for example I might say "if it is raining in Ithaca right now then the President of the United States is a gerbil!" and that is a completely true statement because it happens to be snowing, not raining, in Ithaca right now. But for a lot of folks this doesn't "smell right" because these things are not related to each other, and I want to say that I should only be able to phrase $X to Y$ when there is some sort of meaningful connection called "relevance" between $X$ and $Y$. Well the problem with "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q$" is precisely that the "for all $Q$" must include statements which are not relevant to either $P$ or $neg P$ and therefore cannot be relevant to $P wedge neg P$.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          So, not every logic does this! (There are many different logics based on the rules that you are allowed to use to infer things.)



          In particular, this is called the principle of explosion and the logics which reject it are called paraconsistent logics. Usually to make normal logic into a paraconsistent system you delete one of the following rules:




          1. If we have concluded $X$ then we can conclude, for any $Y$, $X vee Y$, which you can read as "either $X$ or $Y$ (or both)."


          2. If we have concluded both $X vee Y$ and $neg X$, then we can conclude $Y$.



          If you have both of these rules in your arsenal then it is easy to see why knowing both $P$ and $neg P$ would entail any $Q$, just first use $P$ to conclude $P vee Q$ and then use that plus $neg P$ to entail $Q$.



          Since these are standard rules, dropping them from your logic results in a weaker logic: it doesn't prove any new things, it just fails to prove some existing things that the stronger logic has no problem with.



          One motivation why some mathematicians (and philosophers etc.) wish to do this sort of thing has to do with the very shape of this claim "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q.$" Classical logic is very happy to rewrite $X to Y$ as $neg X vee Y$ in a way that enables vacuous consistency, for example I might say "if it is raining in Ithaca right now then the President of the United States is a gerbil!" and that is a completely true statement because it happens to be snowing, not raining, in Ithaca right now. But for a lot of folks this doesn't "smell right" because these things are not related to each other, and I want to say that I should only be able to phrase $X to Y$ when there is some sort of meaningful connection called "relevance" between $X$ and $Y$. Well the problem with "for all $Q$, $(P wedge neg P)to Q$" is precisely that the "for all $Q$" must include statements which are not relevant to either $P$ or $neg P$ and therefore cannot be relevant to $P wedge neg P$.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Dec 27 '18 at 3:09









          CR DrostCR Drost

          1,849811




          1,849811























              0












              $begingroup$

              Think about it this way:



              If we have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash p$ and we also have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash neg p$ (we know we have these because we can assume anything that's inside the premise set)
              then we can move the negation of one of the things inside our premise set onto the right side (since we had a contradiction). It doesn't matter which thing we move outside the premise set, so we can choose to move the $neg q$ outside. This means that



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg neg q$



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash q$



              Notice that we could have actually used just $q$ in our premise set instead of $neg q$, so this means that

              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg q$



              In fact, {$p,neg p$} can imply anything.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$













              • $begingroup$
                Please ask if you have any questions
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:40






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                Sorry if this is a basic question: why does a contradiction allow us to move something from the premise to the right side?
                $endgroup$
                – Alex
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:58






              • 2




                $begingroup$
                @Alex the way I think of it is that if you arrive at a contradiction, then something in your premise set must be wrong. However, you don't necessarily know what is wrong, so you can move the negation of one thing (in the premise set) onto the right side. This may seem a little cheaty, but we aren't breaking any rules as if we were to move the wrong assumption onto the right side and negate it (when I say wrong I mean it isn't helping our proof), then we will just end up with a statement that doesn't help us, but is still logically correct
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:05






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                @Alex I found a much better way of seeing this on wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:06
















              0












              $begingroup$

              Think about it this way:



              If we have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash p$ and we also have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash neg p$ (we know we have these because we can assume anything that's inside the premise set)
              then we can move the negation of one of the things inside our premise set onto the right side (since we had a contradiction). It doesn't matter which thing we move outside the premise set, so we can choose to move the $neg q$ outside. This means that



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg neg q$



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash q$



              Notice that we could have actually used just $q$ in our premise set instead of $neg q$, so this means that

              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg q$



              In fact, {$p,neg p$} can imply anything.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$













              • $begingroup$
                Please ask if you have any questions
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:40






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                Sorry if this is a basic question: why does a contradiction allow us to move something from the premise to the right side?
                $endgroup$
                – Alex
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:58






              • 2




                $begingroup$
                @Alex the way I think of it is that if you arrive at a contradiction, then something in your premise set must be wrong. However, you don't necessarily know what is wrong, so you can move the negation of one thing (in the premise set) onto the right side. This may seem a little cheaty, but we aren't breaking any rules as if we were to move the wrong assumption onto the right side and negate it (when I say wrong I mean it isn't helping our proof), then we will just end up with a statement that doesn't help us, but is still logically correct
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:05






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                @Alex I found a much better way of seeing this on wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:06














              0












              0








              0





              $begingroup$

              Think about it this way:



              If we have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash p$ and we also have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash neg p$ (we know we have these because we can assume anything that's inside the premise set)
              then we can move the negation of one of the things inside our premise set onto the right side (since we had a contradiction). It doesn't matter which thing we move outside the premise set, so we can choose to move the $neg q$ outside. This means that



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg neg q$



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash q$



              Notice that we could have actually used just $q$ in our premise set instead of $neg q$, so this means that

              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg q$



              In fact, {$p,neg p$} can imply anything.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$



              Think about it this way:



              If we have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash p$ and we also have {$p,neg p,neg q$} $vdash neg p$ (we know we have these because we can assume anything that's inside the premise set)
              then we can move the negation of one of the things inside our premise set onto the right side (since we had a contradiction). It doesn't matter which thing we move outside the premise set, so we can choose to move the $neg q$ outside. This means that



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg neg q$



              {$p,neg p$} $vdash q$



              Notice that we could have actually used just $q$ in our premise set instead of $neg q$, so this means that

              {$p,neg p$} $vdash neg q$



              In fact, {$p,neg p$} can imply anything.







              share|cite|improve this answer












              share|cite|improve this answer



              share|cite|improve this answer










              answered Dec 27 '18 at 1:40









              Riley HRiley H

              1046




              1046












              • $begingroup$
                Please ask if you have any questions
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:40






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                Sorry if this is a basic question: why does a contradiction allow us to move something from the premise to the right side?
                $endgroup$
                – Alex
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:58






              • 2




                $begingroup$
                @Alex the way I think of it is that if you arrive at a contradiction, then something in your premise set must be wrong. However, you don't necessarily know what is wrong, so you can move the negation of one thing (in the premise set) onto the right side. This may seem a little cheaty, but we aren't breaking any rules as if we were to move the wrong assumption onto the right side and negate it (when I say wrong I mean it isn't helping our proof), then we will just end up with a statement that doesn't help us, but is still logically correct
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:05






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                @Alex I found a much better way of seeing this on wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:06


















              • $begingroup$
                Please ask if you have any questions
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:40






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                Sorry if this is a basic question: why does a contradiction allow us to move something from the premise to the right side?
                $endgroup$
                – Alex
                Dec 27 '18 at 1:58






              • 2




                $begingroup$
                @Alex the way I think of it is that if you arrive at a contradiction, then something in your premise set must be wrong. However, you don't necessarily know what is wrong, so you can move the negation of one thing (in the premise set) onto the right side. This may seem a little cheaty, but we aren't breaking any rules as if we were to move the wrong assumption onto the right side and negate it (when I say wrong I mean it isn't helping our proof), then we will just end up with a statement that doesn't help us, but is still logically correct
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:05






              • 1




                $begingroup$
                @Alex I found a much better way of seeing this on wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion
                $endgroup$
                – Riley H
                Dec 27 '18 at 2:06
















              $begingroup$
              Please ask if you have any questions
              $endgroup$
              – Riley H
              Dec 27 '18 at 1:40




              $begingroup$
              Please ask if you have any questions
              $endgroup$
              – Riley H
              Dec 27 '18 at 1:40




              1




              1




              $begingroup$
              Sorry if this is a basic question: why does a contradiction allow us to move something from the premise to the right side?
              $endgroup$
              – Alex
              Dec 27 '18 at 1:58




              $begingroup$
              Sorry if this is a basic question: why does a contradiction allow us to move something from the premise to the right side?
              $endgroup$
              – Alex
              Dec 27 '18 at 1:58




              2




              2




              $begingroup$
              @Alex the way I think of it is that if you arrive at a contradiction, then something in your premise set must be wrong. However, you don't necessarily know what is wrong, so you can move the negation of one thing (in the premise set) onto the right side. This may seem a little cheaty, but we aren't breaking any rules as if we were to move the wrong assumption onto the right side and negate it (when I say wrong I mean it isn't helping our proof), then we will just end up with a statement that doesn't help us, but is still logically correct
              $endgroup$
              – Riley H
              Dec 27 '18 at 2:05




              $begingroup$
              @Alex the way I think of it is that if you arrive at a contradiction, then something in your premise set must be wrong. However, you don't necessarily know what is wrong, so you can move the negation of one thing (in the premise set) onto the right side. This may seem a little cheaty, but we aren't breaking any rules as if we were to move the wrong assumption onto the right side and negate it (when I say wrong I mean it isn't helping our proof), then we will just end up with a statement that doesn't help us, but is still logically correct
              $endgroup$
              – Riley H
              Dec 27 '18 at 2:05




              1




              1




              $begingroup$
              @Alex I found a much better way of seeing this on wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion
              $endgroup$
              – Riley H
              Dec 27 '18 at 2:06




              $begingroup$
              @Alex I found a much better way of seeing this on wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion
              $endgroup$
              – Riley H
              Dec 27 '18 at 2:06











              0












              $begingroup$

              To prove $Aimplies [neg A implies B]$ you need only the following elementary methods and rules of natural deduction:





              1. $implies$-Introduction (Conlusion, direct proof)


              2. $neg$-Introduction (Conclusion, proof by contradiction)


              3. $land$-Introduction (Join)


              4. $negneg$-Elimination (Rem DNeg)


              In DC Proof, for example (user comments in blue font):



              enter image description here






              share|cite|improve this answer











              $endgroup$


















                0












                $begingroup$

                To prove $Aimplies [neg A implies B]$ you need only the following elementary methods and rules of natural deduction:





                1. $implies$-Introduction (Conlusion, direct proof)


                2. $neg$-Introduction (Conclusion, proof by contradiction)


                3. $land$-Introduction (Join)


                4. $negneg$-Elimination (Rem DNeg)


                In DC Proof, for example (user comments in blue font):



                enter image description here






                share|cite|improve this answer











                $endgroup$
















                  0












                  0








                  0





                  $begingroup$

                  To prove $Aimplies [neg A implies B]$ you need only the following elementary methods and rules of natural deduction:





                  1. $implies$-Introduction (Conlusion, direct proof)


                  2. $neg$-Introduction (Conclusion, proof by contradiction)


                  3. $land$-Introduction (Join)


                  4. $negneg$-Elimination (Rem DNeg)


                  In DC Proof, for example (user comments in blue font):



                  enter image description here






                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  $endgroup$



                  To prove $Aimplies [neg A implies B]$ you need only the following elementary methods and rules of natural deduction:





                  1. $implies$-Introduction (Conlusion, direct proof)


                  2. $neg$-Introduction (Conclusion, proof by contradiction)


                  3. $land$-Introduction (Join)


                  4. $negneg$-Elimination (Rem DNeg)


                  In DC Proof, for example (user comments in blue font):



                  enter image description here







                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited Dec 27 '18 at 15:26

























                  answered Dec 27 '18 at 14:50









                  Dan ChristensenDan Christensen

                  8,70821835




                  8,70821835















                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Biblatex bibliography style without URLs when DOI exists (in Overleaf with Zotero bibliography)

                      ComboBox Display Member on multiple fields

                      Is it possible to collect Nectar points via Trainline?