When we say two fields are isomorphic, does that just mean they are isomophic as rings? [closed]












10














If we say fields $A$ and $B$ are isomorphic, does that just mean they are isomorphic as rings, or is there something else?










share|cite|improve this question













closed as off-topic by Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039 Dec 14 '18 at 14:04


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.









  • 8




    A field homomorphism is a ring homomorphism between fields - so yes!
    – Dietrich Burde
    Dec 11 '18 at 19:09










  • Please see my comment, which explains just what TonyK's answer means by "field structure".
    – user21820
    Dec 12 '18 at 12:46
















10














If we say fields $A$ and $B$ are isomorphic, does that just mean they are isomorphic as rings, or is there something else?










share|cite|improve this question













closed as off-topic by Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039 Dec 14 '18 at 14:04


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.









  • 8




    A field homomorphism is a ring homomorphism between fields - so yes!
    – Dietrich Burde
    Dec 11 '18 at 19:09










  • Please see my comment, which explains just what TonyK's answer means by "field structure".
    – user21820
    Dec 12 '18 at 12:46














10












10








10







If we say fields $A$ and $B$ are isomorphic, does that just mean they are isomorphic as rings, or is there something else?










share|cite|improve this question













If we say fields $A$ and $B$ are isomorphic, does that just mean they are isomorphic as rings, or is there something else?







abstract-algebra field-theory






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Dec 11 '18 at 18:40









Ovi

12.4k1038111




12.4k1038111




closed as off-topic by Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039 Dec 14 '18 at 14:04


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.




closed as off-topic by Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039 Dec 14 '18 at 14:04


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please provide additional context, which ideally explains why the question is relevant to you and our community. Some forms of context include: background and motivation, relevant definitions, source, possible strategies, your current progress, why the question is interesting or important, etc." – Saad, Gibbs, Xander Henderson, amWhy, user 170039

If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.








  • 8




    A field homomorphism is a ring homomorphism between fields - so yes!
    – Dietrich Burde
    Dec 11 '18 at 19:09










  • Please see my comment, which explains just what TonyK's answer means by "field structure".
    – user21820
    Dec 12 '18 at 12:46














  • 8




    A field homomorphism is a ring homomorphism between fields - so yes!
    – Dietrich Burde
    Dec 11 '18 at 19:09










  • Please see my comment, which explains just what TonyK's answer means by "field structure".
    – user21820
    Dec 12 '18 at 12:46








8




8




A field homomorphism is a ring homomorphism between fields - so yes!
– Dietrich Burde
Dec 11 '18 at 19:09




A field homomorphism is a ring homomorphism between fields - so yes!
– Dietrich Burde
Dec 11 '18 at 19:09












Please see my comment, which explains just what TonyK's answer means by "field structure".
– user21820
Dec 12 '18 at 12:46




Please see my comment, which explains just what TonyK's answer means by "field structure".
– user21820
Dec 12 '18 at 12:46










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















25














In a sense, yes, that is what it means. But not really. When we say two structures $S$ and $T$ of a certain type are isomorphic, we mean that there is a bijection $varphi:Srightarrow T$ which preserves the structure. So, for instance, if $circ$ is a binary operation in the structure, then for $x,yin S$, we have $varphi(xcirc y)=varphi(x)circ varphi(y)$.



It turns out that preserving the ring structure is enough to preserve the field structure; a field is just a commutative ring with inverses, so the property of being a field is preserved if the operations $+$ and $times$ are preserved. Thus two fields are isomorphic if and only if they are isomorphic when considered as rings. But this is a contingent fact, and it's not really what we mean when we say that two fields are isomorphic.



I realise that this view verges on philosophy, and I wouldn't defend it to the death. I am just trying to give an idea of what mathematicians are thinking of when they say isomorphic.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • So in other words, you would want the field isomorphism to include a condition like: if $x ne 0$ then $phi(x) ne 0$ and $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$, right? (Or possibly, if $x ne 0$ and $phi(x) ne 0$ then $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$.)
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 11 '18 at 19:34






  • 7




    I'm not sure I agree with this answer. There is no such thing as a "field structure": a ring is a set with additional structure, and a field is a ring with the additional property that the multiplication operation is invertible away from zero. From this perspective, it's automatic that a homomorphism of fields is just a homomorphism of rings.
    – hunter
    Dec 11 '18 at 22:59






  • 8




    @hunter I think some might call that “property” a “unary operation with a special compatibility condition with multiplication” so that it is sort of a structure.
    – rschwieb
    Dec 12 '18 at 1:48






  • 1




    @user21820 But the field axioms are not universal, you have an implication $xne0$ in it — and so fields do not form a variety in the sense of universal algebra.
    – Joker_vD
    Dec 12 '18 at 14:55






  • 1




    @Joker_vD: I'm using "universal sentence" as defined in standard logic texts (e.g. Rautenberg) and on Math SE. I didn't say we get a universal algebra, but universal theories do have some nice properties. With the original field axioms, not every substructure (ring) of a field is a field. But with the Skolemized field axioms (and if you stipulate $i(0) = 0$), every substructure (closed under $+,-,·,i$) is a field. That is how we think of subfields too. Every universal theory has a term model. What you're referring to are universal Horn formulae.
    – user21820
    Dec 12 '18 at 18:08



















15














They are just isomorphic as rings.



A ring isomorphism already preserves both operations of the field, and it's trivial to prove that a ring isomorphism "preserves inverses," so there's nothing else you could ask of an isomorphism between fields that isn't already there.






share|cite|improve this answer




























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    25














    In a sense, yes, that is what it means. But not really. When we say two structures $S$ and $T$ of a certain type are isomorphic, we mean that there is a bijection $varphi:Srightarrow T$ which preserves the structure. So, for instance, if $circ$ is a binary operation in the structure, then for $x,yin S$, we have $varphi(xcirc y)=varphi(x)circ varphi(y)$.



    It turns out that preserving the ring structure is enough to preserve the field structure; a field is just a commutative ring with inverses, so the property of being a field is preserved if the operations $+$ and $times$ are preserved. Thus two fields are isomorphic if and only if they are isomorphic when considered as rings. But this is a contingent fact, and it's not really what we mean when we say that two fields are isomorphic.



    I realise that this view verges on philosophy, and I wouldn't defend it to the death. I am just trying to give an idea of what mathematicians are thinking of when they say isomorphic.






    share|cite|improve this answer





















    • So in other words, you would want the field isomorphism to include a condition like: if $x ne 0$ then $phi(x) ne 0$ and $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$, right? (Or possibly, if $x ne 0$ and $phi(x) ne 0$ then $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$.)
      – Daniel Schepler
      Dec 11 '18 at 19:34






    • 7




      I'm not sure I agree with this answer. There is no such thing as a "field structure": a ring is a set with additional structure, and a field is a ring with the additional property that the multiplication operation is invertible away from zero. From this perspective, it's automatic that a homomorphism of fields is just a homomorphism of rings.
      – hunter
      Dec 11 '18 at 22:59






    • 8




      @hunter I think some might call that “property” a “unary operation with a special compatibility condition with multiplication” so that it is sort of a structure.
      – rschwieb
      Dec 12 '18 at 1:48






    • 1




      @user21820 But the field axioms are not universal, you have an implication $xne0$ in it — and so fields do not form a variety in the sense of universal algebra.
      – Joker_vD
      Dec 12 '18 at 14:55






    • 1




      @Joker_vD: I'm using "universal sentence" as defined in standard logic texts (e.g. Rautenberg) and on Math SE. I didn't say we get a universal algebra, but universal theories do have some nice properties. With the original field axioms, not every substructure (ring) of a field is a field. But with the Skolemized field axioms (and if you stipulate $i(0) = 0$), every substructure (closed under $+,-,·,i$) is a field. That is how we think of subfields too. Every universal theory has a term model. What you're referring to are universal Horn formulae.
      – user21820
      Dec 12 '18 at 18:08
















    25














    In a sense, yes, that is what it means. But not really. When we say two structures $S$ and $T$ of a certain type are isomorphic, we mean that there is a bijection $varphi:Srightarrow T$ which preserves the structure. So, for instance, if $circ$ is a binary operation in the structure, then for $x,yin S$, we have $varphi(xcirc y)=varphi(x)circ varphi(y)$.



    It turns out that preserving the ring structure is enough to preserve the field structure; a field is just a commutative ring with inverses, so the property of being a field is preserved if the operations $+$ and $times$ are preserved. Thus two fields are isomorphic if and only if they are isomorphic when considered as rings. But this is a contingent fact, and it's not really what we mean when we say that two fields are isomorphic.



    I realise that this view verges on philosophy, and I wouldn't defend it to the death. I am just trying to give an idea of what mathematicians are thinking of when they say isomorphic.






    share|cite|improve this answer





















    • So in other words, you would want the field isomorphism to include a condition like: if $x ne 0$ then $phi(x) ne 0$ and $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$, right? (Or possibly, if $x ne 0$ and $phi(x) ne 0$ then $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$.)
      – Daniel Schepler
      Dec 11 '18 at 19:34






    • 7




      I'm not sure I agree with this answer. There is no such thing as a "field structure": a ring is a set with additional structure, and a field is a ring with the additional property that the multiplication operation is invertible away from zero. From this perspective, it's automatic that a homomorphism of fields is just a homomorphism of rings.
      – hunter
      Dec 11 '18 at 22:59






    • 8




      @hunter I think some might call that “property” a “unary operation with a special compatibility condition with multiplication” so that it is sort of a structure.
      – rschwieb
      Dec 12 '18 at 1:48






    • 1




      @user21820 But the field axioms are not universal, you have an implication $xne0$ in it — and so fields do not form a variety in the sense of universal algebra.
      – Joker_vD
      Dec 12 '18 at 14:55






    • 1




      @Joker_vD: I'm using "universal sentence" as defined in standard logic texts (e.g. Rautenberg) and on Math SE. I didn't say we get a universal algebra, but universal theories do have some nice properties. With the original field axioms, not every substructure (ring) of a field is a field. But with the Skolemized field axioms (and if you stipulate $i(0) = 0$), every substructure (closed under $+,-,·,i$) is a field. That is how we think of subfields too. Every universal theory has a term model. What you're referring to are universal Horn formulae.
      – user21820
      Dec 12 '18 at 18:08














    25












    25








    25






    In a sense, yes, that is what it means. But not really. When we say two structures $S$ and $T$ of a certain type are isomorphic, we mean that there is a bijection $varphi:Srightarrow T$ which preserves the structure. So, for instance, if $circ$ is a binary operation in the structure, then for $x,yin S$, we have $varphi(xcirc y)=varphi(x)circ varphi(y)$.



    It turns out that preserving the ring structure is enough to preserve the field structure; a field is just a commutative ring with inverses, so the property of being a field is preserved if the operations $+$ and $times$ are preserved. Thus two fields are isomorphic if and only if they are isomorphic when considered as rings. But this is a contingent fact, and it's not really what we mean when we say that two fields are isomorphic.



    I realise that this view verges on philosophy, and I wouldn't defend it to the death. I am just trying to give an idea of what mathematicians are thinking of when they say isomorphic.






    share|cite|improve this answer












    In a sense, yes, that is what it means. But not really. When we say two structures $S$ and $T$ of a certain type are isomorphic, we mean that there is a bijection $varphi:Srightarrow T$ which preserves the structure. So, for instance, if $circ$ is a binary operation in the structure, then for $x,yin S$, we have $varphi(xcirc y)=varphi(x)circ varphi(y)$.



    It turns out that preserving the ring structure is enough to preserve the field structure; a field is just a commutative ring with inverses, so the property of being a field is preserved if the operations $+$ and $times$ are preserved. Thus two fields are isomorphic if and only if they are isomorphic when considered as rings. But this is a contingent fact, and it's not really what we mean when we say that two fields are isomorphic.



    I realise that this view verges on philosophy, and I wouldn't defend it to the death. I am just trying to give an idea of what mathematicians are thinking of when they say isomorphic.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Dec 11 '18 at 19:03









    TonyK

    41.5k353132




    41.5k353132












    • So in other words, you would want the field isomorphism to include a condition like: if $x ne 0$ then $phi(x) ne 0$ and $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$, right? (Or possibly, if $x ne 0$ and $phi(x) ne 0$ then $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$.)
      – Daniel Schepler
      Dec 11 '18 at 19:34






    • 7




      I'm not sure I agree with this answer. There is no such thing as a "field structure": a ring is a set with additional structure, and a field is a ring with the additional property that the multiplication operation is invertible away from zero. From this perspective, it's automatic that a homomorphism of fields is just a homomorphism of rings.
      – hunter
      Dec 11 '18 at 22:59






    • 8




      @hunter I think some might call that “property” a “unary operation with a special compatibility condition with multiplication” so that it is sort of a structure.
      – rschwieb
      Dec 12 '18 at 1:48






    • 1




      @user21820 But the field axioms are not universal, you have an implication $xne0$ in it — and so fields do not form a variety in the sense of universal algebra.
      – Joker_vD
      Dec 12 '18 at 14:55






    • 1




      @Joker_vD: I'm using "universal sentence" as defined in standard logic texts (e.g. Rautenberg) and on Math SE. I didn't say we get a universal algebra, but universal theories do have some nice properties. With the original field axioms, not every substructure (ring) of a field is a field. But with the Skolemized field axioms (and if you stipulate $i(0) = 0$), every substructure (closed under $+,-,·,i$) is a field. That is how we think of subfields too. Every universal theory has a term model. What you're referring to are universal Horn formulae.
      – user21820
      Dec 12 '18 at 18:08


















    • So in other words, you would want the field isomorphism to include a condition like: if $x ne 0$ then $phi(x) ne 0$ and $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$, right? (Or possibly, if $x ne 0$ and $phi(x) ne 0$ then $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$.)
      – Daniel Schepler
      Dec 11 '18 at 19:34






    • 7




      I'm not sure I agree with this answer. There is no such thing as a "field structure": a ring is a set with additional structure, and a field is a ring with the additional property that the multiplication operation is invertible away from zero. From this perspective, it's automatic that a homomorphism of fields is just a homomorphism of rings.
      – hunter
      Dec 11 '18 at 22:59






    • 8




      @hunter I think some might call that “property” a “unary operation with a special compatibility condition with multiplication” so that it is sort of a structure.
      – rschwieb
      Dec 12 '18 at 1:48






    • 1




      @user21820 But the field axioms are not universal, you have an implication $xne0$ in it — and so fields do not form a variety in the sense of universal algebra.
      – Joker_vD
      Dec 12 '18 at 14:55






    • 1




      @Joker_vD: I'm using "universal sentence" as defined in standard logic texts (e.g. Rautenberg) and on Math SE. I didn't say we get a universal algebra, but universal theories do have some nice properties. With the original field axioms, not every substructure (ring) of a field is a field. But with the Skolemized field axioms (and if you stipulate $i(0) = 0$), every substructure (closed under $+,-,·,i$) is a field. That is how we think of subfields too. Every universal theory has a term model. What you're referring to are universal Horn formulae.
      – user21820
      Dec 12 '18 at 18:08
















    So in other words, you would want the field isomorphism to include a condition like: if $x ne 0$ then $phi(x) ne 0$ and $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$, right? (Or possibly, if $x ne 0$ and $phi(x) ne 0$ then $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$.)
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 11 '18 at 19:34




    So in other words, you would want the field isomorphism to include a condition like: if $x ne 0$ then $phi(x) ne 0$ and $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$, right? (Or possibly, if $x ne 0$ and $phi(x) ne 0$ then $(phi(x))^{-1} = phi(x^{-1})$.)
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 11 '18 at 19:34




    7




    7




    I'm not sure I agree with this answer. There is no such thing as a "field structure": a ring is a set with additional structure, and a field is a ring with the additional property that the multiplication operation is invertible away from zero. From this perspective, it's automatic that a homomorphism of fields is just a homomorphism of rings.
    – hunter
    Dec 11 '18 at 22:59




    I'm not sure I agree with this answer. There is no such thing as a "field structure": a ring is a set with additional structure, and a field is a ring with the additional property that the multiplication operation is invertible away from zero. From this perspective, it's automatic that a homomorphism of fields is just a homomorphism of rings.
    – hunter
    Dec 11 '18 at 22:59




    8




    8




    @hunter I think some might call that “property” a “unary operation with a special compatibility condition with multiplication” so that it is sort of a structure.
    – rschwieb
    Dec 12 '18 at 1:48




    @hunter I think some might call that “property” a “unary operation with a special compatibility condition with multiplication” so that it is sort of a structure.
    – rschwieb
    Dec 12 '18 at 1:48




    1




    1




    @user21820 But the field axioms are not universal, you have an implication $xne0$ in it — and so fields do not form a variety in the sense of universal algebra.
    – Joker_vD
    Dec 12 '18 at 14:55




    @user21820 But the field axioms are not universal, you have an implication $xne0$ in it — and so fields do not form a variety in the sense of universal algebra.
    – Joker_vD
    Dec 12 '18 at 14:55




    1




    1




    @Joker_vD: I'm using "universal sentence" as defined in standard logic texts (e.g. Rautenberg) and on Math SE. I didn't say we get a universal algebra, but universal theories do have some nice properties. With the original field axioms, not every substructure (ring) of a field is a field. But with the Skolemized field axioms (and if you stipulate $i(0) = 0$), every substructure (closed under $+,-,·,i$) is a field. That is how we think of subfields too. Every universal theory has a term model. What you're referring to are universal Horn formulae.
    – user21820
    Dec 12 '18 at 18:08




    @Joker_vD: I'm using "universal sentence" as defined in standard logic texts (e.g. Rautenberg) and on Math SE. I didn't say we get a universal algebra, but universal theories do have some nice properties. With the original field axioms, not every substructure (ring) of a field is a field. But with the Skolemized field axioms (and if you stipulate $i(0) = 0$), every substructure (closed under $+,-,·,i$) is a field. That is how we think of subfields too. Every universal theory has a term model. What you're referring to are universal Horn formulae.
    – user21820
    Dec 12 '18 at 18:08











    15














    They are just isomorphic as rings.



    A ring isomorphism already preserves both operations of the field, and it's trivial to prove that a ring isomorphism "preserves inverses," so there's nothing else you could ask of an isomorphism between fields that isn't already there.






    share|cite|improve this answer


























      15














      They are just isomorphic as rings.



      A ring isomorphism already preserves both operations of the field, and it's trivial to prove that a ring isomorphism "preserves inverses," so there's nothing else you could ask of an isomorphism between fields that isn't already there.






      share|cite|improve this answer
























        15












        15








        15






        They are just isomorphic as rings.



        A ring isomorphism already preserves both operations of the field, and it's trivial to prove that a ring isomorphism "preserves inverses," so there's nothing else you could ask of an isomorphism between fields that isn't already there.






        share|cite|improve this answer












        They are just isomorphic as rings.



        A ring isomorphism already preserves both operations of the field, and it's trivial to prove that a ring isomorphism "preserves inverses," so there's nothing else you could ask of an isomorphism between fields that isn't already there.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Dec 11 '18 at 18:44









        rschwieb

        105k1299244




        105k1299244















            Popular posts from this blog

            Biblatex bibliography style without URLs when DOI exists (in Overleaf with Zotero bibliography)

            ComboBox Display Member on multiple fields

            Is it possible to collect Nectar points via Trainline?